Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals
Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals
Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals
Ebook104 pages1 hour

Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Rating: 3.5 out of 5 stars

3.5/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Ancient Greek philosophy was divided into three sciences: physics, ethics, and logic. This division is perfectly suitable to the nature of the thing; and the only improvement that can be made in it is to add the principle on which it is based, so that we may both satisfy ourselves of its completeness, and also be able to determine correctly the necessary subdivisions. All rational knowledge is either material or formal: the former considers some object, the latter is concerned only with the form of the understanding and of the reason itself, and with the universal laws of thought in general without distinction of its objects. Formal philosophy is called logic. Material philosophy, however, has to do with determinate objects and the laws to which they are subject, is again twofold; for these laws are either laws of nature or of freedom. The science of the former is physics, that of the latter, ethics; they are also called natural philosophy and moral philosophy respectively.
LanguageEnglish
PublisherPubMe
Release dateJun 19, 2015
ISBN9786051762142
Author

Immanuel Kant

Immanuel Kant was a German philosopher and is known as one of the foremost thinkers of Enlightenment. He is widely recognized for his contributions to metaphysics, epistemology, ethics, and aesthetics.

Read more from Immanuel Kant

Related to Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals

Rating: 3.6033834432330827 out of 5 stars
3.5/5

266 ratings4 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

  • Rating: 3 out of 5 stars
    3/5
    Inasmuch as we can praise Kant's brilliance and analytical rigour, the Metaphysics of Morals falls patently flat if only because he is overextending the gains he has made in the first Critique to apply to the domain of ethics. Any movement from "is" to "ought" (i.e., the shift from ontology to ethics) is going to be fraught with perils. I would say that, from the standpoint of Kant's entire oeuvre, this is his lowest point. That being said, no serious reader in philosophy can bypass this text as it is essential reading in the development of ethics in the transition from the Enlightenment to subsequent Romanticism.
  • Rating: 4 out of 5 stars
    4/5
    Kant is very hard to read, at least for me, however when reading him you discover a first rate mind, that looks very deeply into the human condition. In this book Kant looks for ground to build a system of moral and ethics on. While it has flaws, for its time his conclusions are breath taking.
  • Rating: 4 out of 5 stars
    4/5
    I don't know--this just doesn't come together for me. Kant tries to develop a consistent system of morals in light of reason and will. He starts off though (p143) with "We assume, as a fundamental principle, that no organ for any purpose will be found in the physical constitution of an organized being, except one which is also the fittest and best adapted for that purpose." He is speaking about reason and will as much as any other organ. Another odd tautology: "Innocence is indeed a glorious thing, only it is a pity that it cannot maintain itself well and is easily seduced." He defines God (ok, so here is why the die-hard intellectuals like him) as "the idea of moral perfection." He does have a nugget of truth in his footnotes about why moral teachings fail -- because the teacher does usually not have a consistent grounding of their own and thus fails to present a coherent picture by example. He describes happiness as the one common end and a duty of practical reason. Ends are valued over means and the "one categorical imperative" is "Act only on a maxim by which you can will that it, at the same time, should become a general law." His conclusion of a few paragraphs does summarize everything and is perhaps the first clearly conveyed information. However, much of his work is an attack on straightforward reason.
  • Rating: 4 out of 5 stars
    4/5
    To read Kant is to become acquainted with what it means to take thought seriously. Today it is not uncommon to set up a straw Kant in Phil 101 classes, using either this text or the "Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics," to depict Kant as an incorrigible rationalist reductionist. Still, if you want to read Kant without slogging through the three Critiques, read "Prolegomena," the "Groundwork for the Metaphysics of Morals," and the "Observations on the Feeling of the Beautiful and Sublime;" you’ll discover a thinker with, yes, tremendous intellect, but more importantly, the integrity of genius; and moreover, one who could also be considered (especially in the "Remarks") a fine stylist. Modern thought remains emphatically post-Kantian, even when it rejects his premises or his conclusions; it is still Kant's project to which it reacts. More than any text I know except Wittgenstein's Tractatus, these works by Kant exhibit the absolute rigor and confidence of hard thinking. Reading them slowly, one almost recaptures the sense that, if the difficulties are simply thought through to the end, even the most immovable problems will yield to the irresistible force of the mind. What Kant and Wittgenstein share is a surprising way of drawing limits to thinking in a way that is meant, ultimately, to empower. Kant sought to make clear the power and the limits of human thinking in such a way as to encourage, rather than undermine, confidence in it. The mind may have limits, but for Kant, as for Socrates, everything is gained in *knowing* those limits. His ethics--the real pinnacle of his thought--demonstrate that definite, positive conclusions for action and conduct could follow from such a delimiting. Seen in this way, his thought is a breathtaking synthesis of audacity and humility, and remains as pertinent as it ever was; not because it's incontestable, but because it engages questions most worth contesting, and does so with courage, consistency, and a real capacity for awe.

Book preview

Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysic of Morals - Immanuel Kant

1^book_preview_excerpt.htmlZ]ܸ+zC޼ _ .#qfı(x}fvɓgA5~<==['\9?>>x<=xKO#b(q%x|ILų \4Cxw;8l`>}粽˧-:e#E40joZؘ %sv[cVaNf]{{vK?M&ϘfxK0i~P.M74cfُpR yhzp2,oDq4c5 nbm^\ < Ý;IȢYO[n_@J C5L Ӎ;5ĿF &GzyyM~o2sQ8n&_@hwldN;Oo*;8 I#@Gw: ǻVC(`e -}D^}ATͅJL+&wj_;QWT"xco)F>JQ`cJSXk\qXz"8VSG?0>avK=4ao3/EAcuA씾+:;){\β縞+YW׿g%rr_XraM"loT 9;L)pw(Tb>o_q3ByCre=;MdLJ_Z7xFŲ C(i!kK7"l{492&4=Y4UfZ š3.y'5"cF*!cDb53KsP@3jW0 3+H:P, bJax 7J*„e9Uz mY0i) _Zʊ5+~b;!guwi,+PÁ #pX}[Cwn15B ś "!,r\L@ !PrZfbj%d8 VvEJ=[2Q .,&HH+`DN.4 ?#&*i՚s>'<b)A!>IiiV(G˧AU|ٯ* ,{T^0>msXJy¸̛ ?YY}C (II HtFa$UJtF'qdJOm" !p 1yi:Il6],J}[35Q5UPVb /P@xq^w]~V-n ^Atk&+]Da0BgS_SѫHNx7KE!`҇t%wJ9(SީbO4ӾnC1+VtH+Ö́HSz5l B!퐭%P傱-J뤚*OfHJ"C"CFb (a“)0cgI!3@>J-xA:[( @Z&L.UQ_ @ fu^,8O,&%yH?,KyNeIFI;(zo!:@ cE}N Xy=@00mBB]j^> ؀EĆ:_:3^\ 93KA2em6 .]NZ]Kk3-!u$/+iDƭ@l' M:A Y@?ە4i _jfx("lP^"@DeDM"d(z h ~RjvQ-ò:L'd}gnVMmgE8&?H+8[3g !obN1u6c:2Z"RG_X)M-JC[ٍehqiXj 4#-Un*s&r$IO_aAڸlk,p k4SFİk~SYoI@cg.묱#)ƒUk&b "sJnxG"UkP܊C.L9Pr*й%MOb(jbxjN:k8!Ȕx4 ]O>I xk6E-lu뉄 7njDMXrxRn6 f S7V~S_j_NJzR*3Rxcuiꪢ8wE 2eRm}jiиvdFތo1bJl,m{a+LgWM},01W=6.sxbAc.iX47pl*>ߨW Vv''+Ų ^aMߏPks2*5NJJ|!*fodd9yZ|;ui۷ҝBҚH2\A4آjYD>HflY?A{Fvz.wQ.T]NXgGOʮS+ɝ!~=/ab=B#zH{.6pN5ճBVMK|@zp-"E}I_^(MΤX9uү^A쵧 ,e4c џ}^J󜟭Ca@G>%`2fU m*81Uv=Lb0wPO5qɑh>)%E9mRDZ=v:Tl 9ưa:RW)7AvhRHѕcb)g|\?Ng7A[YXYiIsס`Vzoi,;ds]NEIurϭ1ƋzYQb%kRnc'; >Kw~LQ㦝ɽ6xJL,[_W0~ԱecN/hSU#
Enjoying the preview?
Page 1 of 1