Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana: Rethinking Political Communication in an African Context
The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana: Rethinking Political Communication in an African Context
The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana: Rethinking Political Communication in an African Context
Ebook387 pages5 hours

The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana: Rethinking Political Communication in an African Context

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

This original new book researches into the praxis of this democracy and its media, delving into Ghana’s evolvement, media practice, leadership aspirations, pressure group politics and ethnic and tribal cleavages. Written in accessible language it will provide valuable source material for readers interested in the development of a democratic culture.

A rich data source for students, scholars and researchers on both the African continent and in the diaspora, it examines the growing influence of social media in political discourse and provides an insightful analysis on debates surrounding political communication and its implications for strengthening democratic culture. Its intention is to challenge the intellectual rigour of scholars, academics, researchers and students. The analytical frames it offers are to generate intellectual discourses. 

Provides an overview of the history of the press in Ghana and how that has shaped the current media landscape, and draws attention to the growing influence of social media in political messages and debate.  The historical analysis of the political situation of Ghana and its relationship to the press is informative, comprehensive and stimulating to read.  Ideas discussed are revealing and relevant to current discussions on the contributions of the media to the growth and development of democracy in Ghana in particular – and in Africa as a whole.

The unusual and highly original comparative analytic approach used here is in dealing with the media-democracy paradox through comments and analysis that challenges the orthodoxy of western idealism.  The discussion of media and democracy, with private and state media operating side-by-side in a multiparty democratic setting regulated by a constitution, adds significantly to the wider field of knowledge on the media and democracy.

Primary audience will be academics, scholars, researchers and students – undergraduate and postgraduate – in the humanities and social sciences. Of particular relevance to those in media and communication studies, political science, journalism, cultural studies, postcolonial studies, and historians whose research interests include Ghana.  Also relevant to those with an interest in democracy and development, to media advocacy institutions and policy makers, and to media development experts.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateJun 30, 2020
ISBN9781789382372
The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana: Rethinking Political Communication in an African Context

Related to The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana

Related ebooks

Popular Culture & Media Studies For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    The Media-Democracy Paradox in Ghana - W.S. Dzisah

    1

    Theorizing Media and Democracy

    Introduction

    The relationship between media and democracy in the Information Age is paradoxical, if not unclear. While technological advances have expanded access to information and communication, and facilitated the growth of big media conglomerates, they have also weakened the balance of power between media users and those who control media institutions, undermining a critical aspect of democracy (McChesney 2015). Though Africa still lags behind in terms of the impact of media on its multi-party democratic development, the continent has been lauded for its gradual and positive emergence as a future battleground for technological progress.

    It is on this basis that the central role of the media in nurturing democracy is subjected to various interpretations. This chapter therefore discusses the media’s contribution to building democracy in Ghana and Africa, and how it shapes the thoughts of the governed. It is argued that the media enable voters to exercise their democratic rights by helping them choose between competing interests. The criticality of information and the education it provides to the electorate in making political choices are some of the fundamental principles that underpin public opinion.

    An independent news media is a sine qua non in a democratic society since it helps keep the governors of the governed in check. The government is arguably only a trustee of the collective will of the people. Its actions should, therefore, be regulated by the force of public opinion. The media is arguably the most potent organ to mobilize, shape, assess and represent public opinion. The media and democracy are generally upheld as being inextricably linked (Curran 1995, 2014). Implicitly, it contextualizes how the media assist democracy to flourish or otherwise. In this way, both must be seen as complementary models that bring about a qualitative output in the much-vaunted sphere of democratic politics.

    From a critical theory perspective, Africa and for that matter Ghana, Nigeria, South Africa, Botswana, Kenya and many others have also been refining their modes, methods and application of communication strategies in the evolving theatre of media and democracy. Within these countries, they have a lot to fall on and to learn from other regions, particularly in the Global North. Therefore, their application of aspects of communication such as political communication in media and democracy ought to be discussed within the context of Africa and beyond. The importance of media and democracy to the African and for that matter the Ghanaian presents us with a huge dilemma. The dilemma they present is informed by the complexities of African governance systems as juxtaposed against the western ideal. In dealing with this paradox, one has to look at the diverse cultures, traditions and value systems within which the media–democracy matrix operates and functions.

    While its benefits present African countries practising constitutional multi-party democracy with the necessary elixir to continue, it has also posed numerous challenges as to the most ideal pathway to deal with the paradox of media and democracy. This has become more crucial within the context of explicating the similarities and differences of media and democracy using varied strategies, theories, concepts and models. A key ingredient for dealing with the paradox in the case of Africa and Ghana in particular is the hydra-headed multiple cultures, traditions, value systems and indigenous communication practices. Some of these are considered to be at variance with the western normative ideal. In theorizing media and democracy, one also has to look at the other paradoxes as they relate to how Africans and their governments deal with issues of power and domination. These, arguably, are embedded in economic and political structures, both from the universal point of appreciation and those of African traditional governance systems (Fuchs 2017).

    Again, the media-democracy dilemma is also overburdened by the role of economic power in modern-day social media, as the concept of commodification of media comes into play. How to navigate the transition from traditional media to incorporate digital media platforms such as social media requires a mastery of new political communication strategies and tactics. The aversion for media-democracy debates from the standpoint of neo-liberal and liberal arguments is exacerbated by the centrality of social media as communication and marketing tool, thereby reinforcing the commodification argument. To deal with this paradox in the media-democracy debate from the perspective of Africa and western viewpoints becomes even more daunting. The twists and turns and the evolving dynamics that incorporates the precolonial, the postcolonial and above all postmodernist influences where media, for example, have become social capital and another layer of commodity deepen the myth. Within the postmodern literature, we can argue that media and democracy debates remain sucked in the unending ideological battles across the globe. Attempts to unravel the paradox are being compounded by new digital tools and, as Fuchs (2017) noted, these social media platforms are becoming rather more self-producing platforms where consumers have been transformed beyond the traditional cultural products. What this continues to present to media and democracy is the perpetual paradox and the struggles against the dominant class within capitalist ideology that refuses to seek self-reflection and rather is reinforcing itself as the best and only system.

    Having provided some thoughts on how to theorize media and democracy in the midst of the various perspectives they offer, it must be clear to us that we cannot discuss this all important subject on Africa and particularly on Ghana without touching on the central role of the normative theories of the media. The same applies to other more sophisticated and contemporary theories that deepen the debates about this exciting enterprise. The normative theories such as the Four Theories of the Press by Siebert et al. (1956, 1963) deserve critical discussion in the same way as the variants of Development Media Theory, the Democratic Participant Media Theory, Public Service Model/Theory and the Communitarian Theory (DeFleur and DeFleur 2010; Griffin et al. 2015; Reid 2017; McQuail 1983, 2005, 2010; Hachten 1981, 1992; Diedong and Naaikuur 2015). Within the broader framework, attention has been paid to other traditional liberal theories within the libertarian normative tradition as they relate to the media’s public-sphere role in relation to various centres of power in the context of deepening their democratic contribution. Theories and models governing democracy such as the direct, representative or pluralist democracy have also been engaged with.

    Using the matrix of media and democracy, the essence of theorizing media and democracy is to unpack how communicating politics helps to achieve a certain degree of effect on both the governors and the governed. In modern liberal democracies, there are periodic campaigns where people present themselves for election. While these processes take place at all levels in the political system, the political spectacle is ably assisted by the flow of information. Whatever form this news flow takes is predicated on the expertise and professionalism of those who understand this field of communication. The ability to disseminate messages about events in all facets of democratic politics calls for professionalism, and this expertise could be found in news management and other public relations interventions. In a democracy, the capacity to influence the electorate, pressure groups and other stakeholders is dependent on the dexterity of the communication vehicles deployed. This is why the media are central to democracy because their political communication abilities have the potency to impact both positively and negatively on the democratic project as a whole.

    With the emergence of social media, the complexities of media influence and effect in democracy have increased. How the media reinforce stereotypes or revitalizes emerging dynamics as to their multiple roles in changing attitudes, moulding behaviour and converting even the most disinterested audiences to embrace political participation and decision making is traceable to unpredictable power of political communication. Commenting on the effects of communication in a democracy, McQuail asserts:

    [T]he effects of mass communication in election campaigns may seem inconsistent with the reality of contemporary political campaigning in which communication strategies are planned in fine detail by a myriad of advisers and professional publicists […] especially by those in media advertising. The fact is that even though the chances of decisively influencing the outcome of an election by means of communication are usually quite small.

    (2005: 526)

    We need to explore the various theories, concepts and models of media and democracy and interrogate their importance. The fast pace of media development has been necessitated by digital media technologies, which means that the application of various strategies for media and democracy imperatives deserves a rethink. This rethink is essential because theorizing media and democracy in the context of Africa as juxtaposed against the Global North calls for meandering through the various strands.

    The democracy debate

    Fukuyama posited that of all the forms of government that have been a part of human existence, from theocracies and monarchies to aristocracies, and from fascism to communism in the twentieth century, ‘the only government that has survived to the end of the twentieth century has been liberal democracy’ (1992: 45). Liberal democracy, according to Fukuyama, is representative democracy and this is also referred to as constitutional and pluralist democracy. He adds, ‘What is emerging victorious […] is not so much liberal practice, as the liberal idea. For a very large part of the world, there is now no ideology with pretensions to challenge liberal democracy’ (1992: 45).

    But George (2013), argues that scholars no longer take seriously the idea that the end of the Cold War would result in ‘successive waves of democratization that would funnel the affected countries down a single, liberal democratic course’ (p. 49). In spite of this counter-argument by George, Fukuyama (1992) further asserts that liberal democracy is a form of rule in which the citizens are free to ‘choose their own governments through periodic, free and fair, secret-ballot, multiparty elections, on the basis of universal and equal adult suffrage’ (1992: 43). He points out, however, that liberal democracy alone does not guarantee equal participation and rights. Furthermore, the fulcrum of liberalism is its emphasis on pluralism, which not only allows individual freedoms, but also is most restricted to the organization of the market as the main elixir for addressing the needs of society (Gronvall 2014; Hallin and Mancini 2004). But this cannot be taken to be wholly ideal or essential for democracy, in that pluralism or representation has been reduced to holding periodic elections (Stromback 2005). Besides, it misguidedly emphasizes rights and freedoms in the context of the tangible and intangible goods in the free market place as representing liberalism (McChesney 2015).

    In as much as Fukuyama (1992) established a theoretical basis for liberal democracy as the only feasible model to have successfully survived ideological battles and practices, African scholars such as Nyamnjoh (2005) and Stromback (2005) disagree with the assertion that using periodic elections is a means to arrive at the democratic paradise as preached by liberal theorists. Nyamnjoh views this kind of democracy as ‘face-powder democracy’. A real democratic culture, he insists, must be seen beyond the electorate just exercising their franchise. Democracy, Nyamnjoh argues, ‘means more than the occasional election of leaders who excel in callous indifference to the predicaments of their people’ (2005: 24).

    Liberal democracy, which Fukuyama (1992) also contends to be reflective of modern representative government, has been criticized by others as inferior to the participatory democracy (Direct Democracy) of the Athenian ideal. For example, according to Dunn (1993), democracy is

    the old but vigorous idea that in human political communities, it ought to be ordinary people (the adult citizens), and not the extra-ordinary people who rule. The power and appeal of the idea come from its promise to render the life of a community something willed and chosen to turn the social and political existences that human beings share into a texture of consciously intended communication. In a democracy, the people (the demos), its human members decide what is to be done, and in so deciding they take their destiny into their own hands.

    (1993: v–vi)

    In providing a further insight into the democratic ideal, Dunn (1993) insists that modern liberal democracy does not offer its citizens the right to decide what is to be done and therefore they do not have their destiny in their own hands. He adds, ‘[T]hey do not because they cannot’ (Dunn 1993: v–vi). It is evident that under the traditional participatory democracy, the citizens using the majoritarian principle are part of the decision-making process. By implication, Dunn is of the view that the participatory democracy of the early Greek states could not be attained in contemporary democracy due to certain inhibiting factors. It, therefore, strengthens the point that there is no utopian situation in reference to the type of democracy best suited for mankind.

    Dunn, however, fails to note that Athenian democracy is also fundamentally flawed because women, the low-born and slaves had no part in it. A slave-owning democracy is a contradiction per se. But he sees the Athenian democracy as an ‘extraordinary invention’ because it allows for freedom for the citizens, insisting on the definition of the citizen that excludes women and slaves (Dunn 1993: 424). It is also imperative for us to understand how it was suitable at the time for such an ideal to work. What Dunn fails to see in ‘Direct Democracy’ is the obviously small populations and settlements around which the system was interwoven. But as noted by Rousseau, with increases in population and huge settlements springing up, the Athenian system is close to impossibility in any modern democratic environment. ‘Direct democracy, the participation in the agora, is suited only to small states and organisations in which the people find it easy to meet and in which every citizen can easily get to know all others’ (Keane 1994: 169). As noted by Plato, the participatory ideal amounted to imposing ‘mediocrity over excellence, amateurism over professionalism, anarchy over order, in short, ignorance over true knowledge’ (Drah 1996: 53; Stromback 2005).

    However, major weaknesses identified in its practice are arguably responsible for democratic improvements that have propelled the human race to the modern liberal and other democratic systems. If indeed it is so, then the modern liberal representative democracy in which the majority are passive actors cannot be said to satisfy the criteria of opinions, freedoms and rights of expression and assembly in anyway. How representative are the elite who are free from ignorance and are knowledgeable compared with the illiterate and uninformed citizen? Worthy of note is the major shift in democratic development between the sixteenth and mid-eighteenth centuries that rendered the Athenian prescription nugatory. It was considered the most inimical form of government, in for example England and other parts of Europe by the aristocratic and propertied classes. The Lockean maxim of ‘no taxation without representation’ finally shut the door on the Aristotelian prescription of a form of government that is ostensibly conducted with the intention to benefit the poor (Moore Jr 1966). In its place a representative government was born. Modern representative democracy was seized by the aristocracy and the middle class.

    The revolutions that swept across the world in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, the American and the French versions being reference points in modern history, are noted for their attempt to reorder a system believed to have been appropriated by the middle class (Reid 2017; Mill 1962). While the wheels of representative democracy roll on to include the ordinary people, by courtesy of revolutionary upheavals, critics like John Stuart Mill (1962) and Alexis de Tocqueville (1945) were, in hindsight, quick to point to the dangers of the exclusion of the minority affluent class. Mill’s philosophical arguments for democratic practice are two sets of ideas that he claims have been misguidedly conflated. He refers to the ‘pure idea of democracy’ that he defines as ‘the government of the whole people equally represented’ and ‘democracy as commonly conceived and hitherto practised’, which is ‘the government of the whole people, exclusively represented’ (1962: 256–57). According to Mill, the first is ‘synonymous with the equality of all citizens’, while the second strangely confounded with the first ‘is a government of privilege, in favour of the numerical majority, who alone possess practically any voice in the state’ resulting in the ‘complete disfranchisement of minorities’ (Mill 1962: 256–57). The articulation of the concerns of the privileged and educated classes about the ‘tyranny of the majority’ is seen as an attempt to restore some credibility to a discredited privileged class (Mill 1962: 256–57).

    The contention is that individual talents and excellence could flourish best under an enlightened, aristocratic monarchy. But both are quick to admit that a society’s average intelligence is a function of the active participation of its members in public affairs. In the absence of such participation, people would become selfish and even anomic. It needs to be pointed out that whereas for de Tocqueville (1945) and other French liberals, liberty is the condition of intellectual and cultural progress, for Mill, the condition is active participation. Mill states:

    [T]he ideally best form of government is that in which […]. Every citizen [is], at least occasionally, called on to take an actual part in the government, by the personal discharge of some public function, local or general.

    (1962: 195)

    Mill’s argument if put in the context of the time is an attempt to distinguish ‘false’ from ‘true’ democracy. The former constituted an imposition of majority rule, while the latter is institutionalized through representative government, which, in turn, accommodates minority sentiments and opinions.

    But as Keane (1994, 2003) and Reid (2017) explain, the concept of democracy cannot be taken to explain whatever it is thought to be. Keane argues that democracy is normative, in that it follows a clear set of rules and has elemental implications. He explains that the normative implications and procedural processes mean ‘who is authorised to make collective decisions and through which procedures such decisions are to be made, regardless of the areas of life in which democracy is practised’ (1994: 168). Unlike Plato’s argument of mediocrity and ignorance ruling over knowledge and excellence, Keane sees the concept of democracy as a combination of clear procedures that leads to consensus building. In effect, the ultimate in democratic participation is capacity building that ensures qualitative and quantitative involvement of all segments of society in the process.

    McNair (2003, 2018), writing on democratic participation, also recognizes the normative principle of equal participation through universal adult suffrage irrespective of status in the society. Constitutional provisions and guarantees, he notes, provide some clarity in the performance and discharge of functions in a democracy and ensures alternatives. He argues that democracy’s main vitality is an agreed set of procedures and rules governing the conduct of elections, the behaviour of those who win them and the legitimate activities of dissenters (McNair 2018). He also argues for a sizeable percentage of the population being engaged in the democratic process in order to give it that broad appeal, acceptance and participation. McNair adds that democracy ought to provide the necessary political choices for the electorate among the competing political parties, and the election of the candidates only through rational and informed decisions of the electorate (McNair 2018). Garnham (1992) also affirms this position articulated by McNair when he argues that democracy not only deals with freedom but also the knowledge necessary to activate choices through political judgement of the various alternatives opened to them. He asserts:

    [T]he rights and duties of a citizen are in large part defined in terms of freedom of assembly and freedom to impart and receive information. Without such freedoms it would be impossible for citizens to possess knowledge of the views of others necessary to reach agreements between themselves, whether consensual or majoritarian, as to either social means or ends; to possess knowledge of the actions of those to whom executive responsibilities are delegated so as to make them accountable; to posses knowledge of the external environment necessary to arrive at appropriate judgement of both personal and social interests.

    (Garnham 1992: 364)

    The rationality argument resonates with the position of Mill. His contention is that society’s average intelligence and active participation in the democratic process is:

    The first element of good government […] being the virtue and intelligence of the human beings composing the community, the most important point of excellence which any form of government can possess is to promote the virtue and intelligence of the people themselves.

    (1962: 195)

    As we debate the essential features of a democracy model, it is only prudent to touch on the livewire of modern liberal ideas as represented by the political party system. We must recall McNair’s references to the liberal idea as they provide for the necessary political choices among the electorate through competing political parties (2018). This idea of political parties or divisions has been fully accounted for by Maier (1993: 135). He traces it to eighteenth-century England where political friends in parliament ensured the acceptance of common policies and secured the offices they wanted. Thus, the political party gradually ‘made politics into a predictable living and an instrument of governance’ (Maier 1993: 135). Maier argues that the institutionalization of political parties in a democracy has helped transform ‘opposition from conspiracy into acceptable dissent’ and therefore provides a vital channel for an otherwise virulent and potentially lethal rivalry into a workaday and tolerable antagonism of ‘ins and outs’ (Maier 1993: 135). A further boost to the liberal idea is captured by Ciaglia (2016) and Keane (1994, 2003) about the need to institutionalize divisions of state and civil society for more open and deliberative processes. For example, Keane argues for a

    self organising (international) civil society which is coordinated and generated by multilayered (supra-national) state institutions, which are in turn held permanently accountable to civil society by mechanisms – political parties, legislatures, communications media – which keep open the channels between state and social institutions.

    (1994: 169)

    Sociologists like Auguste Comte and Emile Durkheim, according to Maier (1993), also argue very forcefully for a strong civil society to shape the structure of democratic politics. They proposed the ‘organisation of civil society to stabilize the fast advancing democratic politics’ (Maier 1993: 132). This view is shared by Holmes when he states the position of theorists in Europe and America on the power of the state that has to be curtailed. He argues that if the state is an agent of coercion to be restricted, then civil society must be seen as a reflexive sphere of freedom that must be enlarged (Holmes 1990).

    Edwards (2011) and Comaroff and Comaroff (1999) also applaud the organization of civil society in a democracy, arguing that has been to protect citizens liberty and to prevent any abuse of political power by the elected officials. However, they view its place in modern western liberal societies as part of the free market capitalist order designed to curtail the power of society by ‘trumpeting instead the uncompromising autonomy of the individual, rights-bearing, physically discrete, monied, market-driven, materially inviolate human subject’ (cited in Nyamnjoh 2005: 29). A major drawback on checks to unrestrained use of political power, is the shift of power concentration within the social polity into the hands of a powerful minority, who claims to represent civil society.

    Despite the plausible arguments and claims to the utopian formulations of liberal democratic thought and practice, Keane warns of the dangers in celebrating the liberal idea or the representative parliamentary democracy as the ‘alpha and omega’ of political forms (1994: 169). He attacks modern democratic practices and the loud claims in the western world to democratic idealism, as a semblance of ‘a homeless drunk staggering uncertainly in search of a lamp-post for support if not illumination’ (1994: 170–71). What Keane tries to argue is located within the philosophical basis of the substantive grounding principle of Tom Paine, Mill and Locke’s natural rights maxim, and the Marxian ideology of the triumph of authentic democracy as derived from the class struggle. The ongoing struggle and debates as to the imperfections of the liberal idea, and the cries and echoes of the world’s majority population still smarting under the shackles of poverty and deprivation, even after the collapse of communism in eastern Europe and other parts of the world, remains a blot on the conscience of the purists of the flawless liberal idea and practice.

    It stands to reason, then, that Fukuyama’s argument, which projects the liberal idea as the unchallenged ideology into the new millennium, is in need of re-examination. According to McChesney (2000, 2015), modern-day democracy as a term has been so widely used that ‘it has lost much of its specificity and meaning’ (McChesney 2000: 4). He laments the abuse of the concept of democracy that now even applies to tangible and intangible products. Products consumed by many in modern times are referred to as ‘democratic’ while those by a tiny minority are considered ‘undemocratic’. As if this was not enough, McChesney also points out the constant reference to anything good being ‘democratic’ while offensive behaviour is described in unpalatable terms. Words like ‘Fascist’ or ‘Hitler-like’ are used to describe ‘negative behaviour regardless of any actual relationship to the Third Reich or fascist politics or politics at all’ (McChesney 2000: 4). Using the United States as a classic example, he questions its characterization as a democracy. It is his view that this description of the United States as being democratic has to be properly evaluated based on the ‘assumptions and values of the person making the claim’ (McChesney 2000: 4).

    McChesney is quick to add that the reference to the United States as a democracy is premised on the

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1