Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Why Parties?: A Second Look
Why Parties?: A Second Look
Why Parties?: A Second Look
Ebook629 pages8 hours

Why Parties?: A Second Look

Rating: 3 out of 5 stars

3/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Since its first appearance fifteen years ago, Why Parties? has become essential reading for anyone wishing to understand the nature of American political parties. In the interim, the party system has undergone some radical changes. In this landmark book, now rewritten for the new millennium, John H. Aldrich goes beyond the clamor of arguments over whether American political parties are in resurgence or decline and undertakes a wholesale reexamination of the foundations of the American party system.

Surveying critical episodes in the development of American political parties—from their formation in the 1790s to the Civil War—Aldrich shows how they serve to combat three fundamental problems of democracy: how to regulate the number of people seeking public office, how to mobilize voters, and how to achieve and maintain the majorities needed to accomplish goals once in office. Aldrich brings this innovative account up to the present by looking at the profound changes in the character of political parties since World War II, especially in light of ongoing contemporary transformations, including the rise of the Republican Party in the South, and what those changes accomplish, such as the Obama Health Care plan. Finally, Why Parties? A Second Look offers a fuller consideration of party systems in general, especially the two-party system in the United States, and explains why this system is necessary for effective democracy.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateJul 24, 2012
ISBN9780226012759
Why Parties?: A Second Look

Read more from John H. Aldrich

Related to Why Parties?

Related ebooks

United States History For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Why Parties?

Rating: 3 out of 5 stars
3/5

1 rating0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Why Parties? - John H. Aldrich

    JOHN H. ALDRICH is the Pfizer-Pratt University Professor of Political Science at Duke University. He is the author and coauthor of numerous books and articles, as well as a Fellow of the American Academy of Arts and Sciences and recipient of the American Political Science Association’s Samuel J. Eldersveld Career Achievement Award.

    The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637

    The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London

    © 1995, 2011 by The University of Chicago

    All rights reserved. Published 2011.

    Printed in the United States of America

    20 19 18 17 16 15 14 13 12 11           1 2 3 4 5

    ISBN-13: 978-0-226-01273-5 (cloth)

    ISBN-13: 978-0-226-01274-2 (paper)

    ISBN-10: 0-226-01273-5 (cloth)

    ISBN-10: 0-226-01274-3 (paper)

    ISBN-13: 978-0-226-01275-9 (e-book)

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Aldrich, John Herbert, 1947–

    Why parties? : a second look / John H. Aldrich.

    p. cm. — (Chicago studies in American politics)

    Includes bibliographical references and index.

    ISBN-13: 978-0-226-01273-5 (hardcover : alk. paper)

    ISBN-10: 0-226-01273-5 (hardcover : alk. paper)

    ISBN-13: 978-0-226-01274-2 (pbk. : alk. paper)

    ISBN-10: 0-226-01274-3 (pbk. : alk. paper) 1. Political parties—United

    States—History. 2. United States—Politics and government. I. Title. II. Series: Chicago studies in American politics.

    JK2261.A458 2011

    324.273—dc22

    2010042778

    This paper meets the requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992 (Permanence of Paper).

    WHY PARTIES?

    A Second Look

    JOHN H. ALDRICH

    THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO PRESS

    Chicago and London

    CHICAGO STUDIES IN AMERICAN POLITICS

    A series edited by Benjamin I. Page, Susan Herbst, Lawrence R. Jacobs, and James Druckman

    Also in the series:

    Selling Fear: Counterterrorism, the Media, and Public Opinion by Brigitte L. Nacos, Yaeli Bloch-Elkon, and Robert Y. Shapiro

    News That Matters: Television and American Opinion, Updated Edition by Shanto Iyengar and Donald R. Kinder

    Obama’s Race: The 2008 Election and the Dream of a Post-Racial America by Michael Tesler and David O. Sears

    Filibustering: A Political History of Obstruction in the House and Senate by Gregory Koger

    In Time of War: Understanding American Public Opinion from World War II to Iraq by Adam J. Berinisky

    Us Against Them: Ethnocentric Foundations of American Opinion by Donald R. Kinder and Cindy D. Kam

    The Partisan Sort: How Liberals Became Democrats and Conservatives Became Republicans by Matthew Levendusky

    Democracy at Risk: How Terrorist Threats Affect the Public by Jennifer L. Merolla and Elizabeth J. Zechmeister

    Agendas and Instability in American Politics, Second Edition by Frank R. Baumgartner and Bryan D. Jones

    The Private Abuse of the Public Interest by Lawrence D. Brown and Lawrence R. Jacobs

    The Party Decides: Presidential Nominations Before and After Reform by Marty Cohen, David Karol, Hans Noel, and John Zaller

    Same Sex, Different Politics: Success and Failure in the Struggles over Gay Rights by Gary Mucciaroni

    In memory of

    Herbert and Ruth Aldrich

    and Robert and Irene Aldrich

    CONTENTS

    Acknowledgments

    PART 1 POLITICAL PARTIES AND DEMOCRACY

    1 Politics and Parties in America

    2 Why Parties Form

    PART 2 PARTY FORMATION IN AMERICA, 1790–1860

    Prologue

    3 Founding the First Parties Institutions and Social Choice

    4 Jacksonian Democracy The Mass Party and Collective Action

    5 Whigs and Republicans Institutions, Issue Agendas, and Ambition

    PART 3 THE NEW POLITICAL PARTY IN CONTEMPORARY AMERICA

    Prologue

    6 Party Activists and Partisan Cleavages

    7 Political Parties and Governance

    8 The Critical Era of the 1960s

    PART 4 CONCLUSIONS

    9 Political Parties, Historical Dynamics, and Democratic Politics

    Notes

    References

    Index

    ACKNOWLEDGMENTS

    Research, and the publications it produces, is a collective enterprise. This fact is especially true for this book, which represents the combination, and culmination, of several different projects. Therefore these acknowledgments run long, and I am certain I have forgotten to note the help and advice of several people. To them, please accept my apologies.

    A large number of institutions provided substantial assistance. The research reported in this book has no clear starting point, but one strong candidate for beginnings is the research I did with the support of the National Science Foundation (SES-8108548). Both the University of Minnesota and Duke University provided grants and generous leaves, and both added supportive and congenial working environments, as well as the advice and assistance of many of their members and staffs. Many of the data used in this project were made available through the University of Michigan’s Inter-university Consortium for Political and Social Research and the National Elections Studies. A great many university departments (mostly, but happily not always, political science departments) suffered through presentations of various parts of this project. Among them are Carnegie Mellon; the University of California (Davis, Los Angeles, and San Diego); California Institute of Technology; the University of Florida; the University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill; Stanford; the University of Rochester; Wisconsin; Yale; and of course Minnesota and Duke. Two institutions deserve special notes of appreciation. The Center for Advanced Study in the Behavioral Sciences (with, in my case, support from NSF, BNS87–00864) provided its usual stimulating intellectual and collegial environment, making for the most enjoyable and rewarding year of my professional life. Phil Converse, Bob Scott, and entire staff, and of course an amazing collection of fellows made it so. The Department of Government at Harvard offered me a rare and special week to discuss this book. Special thanks to Jim Alt and Ken Shepsle for that opportunity and to the Harvard community for helping to make me spend a few more years completing this book, and making the result much better.

    I have had the good fortune to learn about politics and political parties from some of the masters of the subject, whether as formal teachers or as colleagues. John Kessel trained me uncommonly well early on, and he has remained a constant source of wisdom and, I am pleased to say, friendship throughout my professional career. Each department where I have worked has provided a major figure on party politics whose influence should be evident throughout this book. My appreciation therefore to Joe Schlesinger and Frank Sorauf. Allan Kornberg not only served that role at Duke but made Duke attractive and welcoming to me and a wonderful place to live and work. Bill Riker’s impact is perhaps most evident of all, but even that greatly understates his importance to me, as to so many others.

    Many people have offered substantial comments on parts of the work in progress. These include Lance Banning, David Baron, Bob Bates, Ira Berlin, Bill Bianco, David Brady, Dean Burnham, David Canon, Gary Cox, John Ferejohn, Mo Fiorina, Ruth Grant, Gary Jacobson, Cal Jillson, Bill Keech, Morgan Kousser, Keith Krehbiel, Peter Lange, Matt McCubbins, Terry Moe, Mike Munger, Dick Niemi, Sam Popkin, Wendy Rahn, Tom Schwartz, Lloyd Shapley, Theda Skocpol, John Sullivan, Jack Walker (whose untimely passing left too much unsaid), Tom Weko, Rick Wilson—and the list goes on. Michael Gillespie listened to my often breathless meanderings as we ran, as well as in more usual venues, and he always had sound advice and insightful facts and opinions to offer, as well as detailed comments. Barry Weingast is quite remarkable. While he has, of course, a lot to offer, what makes him special is both his ability to see to the heart of the matter quickly, and when he has criticisms, to make them be seen positively rather than as the devastating critiques they could be. Two stand out for their genuine friendship and professionalism. Dave Rohde and Ken Shepsle were not just willing to read and comment as often as asked, they also listened, supported, and discussed for many hours over many years.

    Another long list of people provided more direct assistance in this project—rather embarrassing, because some did so as graduate students and are now senior faculty. Mike McGinnis and John Williams fit that bill most directly. Wendy Rahn soon will. Mike Alvarez, Jacquie Pfeffer, Pat Sellers, and Mat Schousen provided more than merely their fine assistance at Duke. A special note of thanks, as well, to Jim Granato, Michael Layton, and Regina Smyth, as well as to students who read drafts of chapters in a course. Ben Page and Charles Stewart read the manuscript with care and strengthened it considerably.

    None of these institutions and none of these people, mentioned and unmentioned, have any responsibility for the content of this book. At the University of Chicago Press, John Tryneski, Alice Bennett, and the rest of the staff are, however, responsible. They are responsible for bringing this book to reality, making it as attractive as it is, and making it, clearly, a better book.

    My family is the reason I have achieved whatever I have accomplished. Cindy is the love of my life and my best friend. She has made my entire adult life joyful. It is hard to believe that David is about to leave us as an adult, although he is in many ways already mature. My appreciation for the love, caring, and wisdom my parents have always given me grows every year. Mom and Dad, it is my honor and privilege to dedicate this book, with love, to you.

    THE NEW EDITION

    One of my greatest professional pleasures has been my good fortune to get to work with some wonderful people who are (or were) graduate students. This has always been true, and remains so as I look back over the process leading to this revision. I particularly would like to thank John Griffin, Brad Gomez, and Jeff Grynaviski for work they did on projects that appear in this revised version, but even more for their own work that has helped shape my thinking over the past fifteen years. Vicky DeFrancesco Soto, Jill Rickershouser Carvalho, Monique Lyle, and Jennifer Merolla not only began as students and became friends, but they also pushed my thinking in a number of very helpful ways. Then there are the comparativists: Alberto Dias, Renan Levine, Beatriz Magaloni, Tom Scotto, Laura Stephenson, and Liz Zechmeister. To them, and to Paul Abramson, Andre Blais, Abraham Diskin, and Indridi Indridason, I propose that the next version will show more full integration into comparative themes. Recent and current graduate students who have done work more particularly for this book—even while starting to turn my thinking much as did John, Brad, and Jeff—include Michael Brady, Brad Bishop, Chris DeSante, Rebecca Hatch, Dan Lee, Ian McDonald, Jacob Montgomery, Brendan Nyhan, Brittany Perry, David Sparks, and Michael Tofias. Special thanks go to David Brady for, among other things, making it possible for me to spend time at the Hoover Institution, Stanford University, an unparalleled place to think and write, and to Norm Schofield for working at such a spectacular level on many of the same problems that interest me. Gary Cox, Mo Fiorina, Mat McCubbins, Ken Shepsle, and Barry Weingast have both pushed and pulled me along, perhaps without their noticing. But of all of these, Dave Rohde has been friend and colleague in virtually every aspect of the revisions of this book, far beyond what anyone could ever ask, including reading the revisions and improving them. John Tryneski remains both a fine editor and friend, but I was especially pleased to get to know Kailee Kremer and have her improve the manuscript so much.

    Much has happened in the fifteen years since Why Parties? was first published. David has not only matured to be a remarkable young (or not so very young) adult, but he has added Whitney to our family. Cindy simply remains the center and greatest joy and love of my life. Sadly, my mother and father, to whom the first edition was dedicated, have both passed on, as have all of their generation in my family, and all but one in Cindy’s. Thus, I dedicate this book to the memory of all of them but in particular to the memory of Cindy’s and my parents.

    PART ONE

    POLITICAL PARTIES AND DEMOCRACY

    1

    POLITICS AND PARTIES IN AMERICA

    Political parties lie at the heart of American politics.¹ E. E. Schattschneider (1942, 1) claimed that political parties created democracy, and . . . democracy is unthinkable save in terms of parties. A fair, if minimal, paraphrase would be to say that democracy is unworkable save in terms of parties. All democracies that are Madisonian, extended republics, which is to say all democratic nations, have political parties. To be truly democratic it is necessary for any nation’s leadership to be harnessed to public desires and aspirations, at least in some very general sense. The elected leaders, being granted political power by the public, must ultimately be held accountable to that public. It may be that each official can be held accountable for his or her own personal actions by the constituency that elects and reelects that offi-cial. But government policy is determined by the collective actions of many individual officeholders. No one person either can or should be held accountable for actions taken by the House, Senate, and president together. The political party as a collective enterprise, organizing competition for the full range of offices, provides the only means for holding elected officials responsible for what they do collectively. Morris P. Fiorina has written (1980, 26) that the only way collective responsibility has ever existed, and can exist, given our institutions, is through the agency of the political party; in American politics, responsibility requires cohesive parties.

    But perhaps there is more. The scholars mentioned above used the plural, parties. It may be, as V. O. Key Jr. argued (1949), that at least two parties are necessary, that it is the plural parties that lie at the heart of, that make workable, and that provide responsibility for democracy. Indeed, we might have to go even further. It may not be the mere presence of two parties at any one time that matters, for sometimes and in some places parties arise and then disappear from electoral competitiveness rapidly, as the American Independent Party and the Reform Party did in the United States in the 1960s and 1990s, respectively. What matters is the sustained competition that comes from the interaction between or among durable parties, such that it is the fact that any winning party must seriously consider the prospect of losing an election before democracy becomes tenable. A necessary condition for effective democracy, in this view, is that there must be a party system, an ongoing set of parties in sustained competition for access to power.

    Of course, to think about a system of parties requires understanding the basis of individual political parties. Most of this book examines why the political party exists. It is important to know what the answer to this question is, because it is then a much shorter step than before toward understanding why a party system exists, and hence why some democracies are tenable and potentially durable. In this chapter, we begin by examining the political party and the elements that go into a theory of the political party, from which we can then consider what a party system might be.

    THE POLITICAL PARTY

    With the ability to shape competition for elected office comes responsibility. Many people, whether academics, commentators, politicians, or members of the public, place the political ills of the contemporary scene—a government seemingly unable to solve critical problems and a public distrustful of, apathetic toward, or alienated from politics—on the failures of the two great American parties. Members of Congress are too concerned with their own reelection, in this view, to be able or willing to think of the public good. The president worries about his personal popularity, spends too little time leading the nation, and when he does turn to Congress, finds it impossible to forge majorities—primarily partisan majorities—to pass his own initiatives or to form workable compromises with Congress. Elections are candidate centered, turning on personality, image, and the latest, cleverest ad. Party platforms are little more than the first order of business at national conventions, only to be passed quickly and, party leaders hope, without controversy or media attention, so that the convention can turn to more important business. Ultimate blame for each of these rests, from this perspective, on the major American party.

    With few, if important, exceptions, in the 1970s and 1980s the scholarly study of American parties turned from foundational theory to an examination of what appeared to be the central set of issues of the day concerning political parties: party decline, decay, and decomposition.² Since then, parties have revitalized. But now there are new ills—extremely polarized red and blue politics, bitter public debates that are essentially demagoguery, intractability, and failure to find compromise regardless of the consequences for the public. Where is the bipartisanship of that era of decline, decay, and decomposition? Parties are, in this view, the problem, whether they are too weak or too strong. And yet, whether stronger or weaker, they are there, and thoughtful observers see them as essential.

    To address these two questions—how do we understand and evaluate political parties, and how do we understand their role in democracy—I return to consider the foundations of the major American political party and the two-party system (or, more generally, the multiparty system). My basic argument is that the major political party is the creature of the politicians, the partisan activist, and the ambitious office seeker and officeholder. They have created and maintained, used or abused, reformed or ignored the political party when doing so has furthered their goals and ambitions. The political party is thus an endogenous institution—an institution shaped by these political actors. Whatever its strength or weakness, whatever its form and role, it is the ambitious politicians’ creation.

    These politicians, we must understand from the outset, do not have partisan goals per se. Rather, they have more personal and fundamental goals, and the party is only the instrument for achieving them. Their goals are several and come in various combinations. Following Richard Fenno (1973), they include most basically the desire to have a long and successful career in political office, but they also encompass the desire to achieve policy ends and to attain power and prestige within the government. These goals are to be sought in government, not in parties, but they are goals that at times have best been realized through the parties. The parties are, as we will see, shaped by these goals in their various combinations, and particularly in the problems politicians most typically encounter when seeking to achieve their goals. Thus, there are three goals, three problems, and three reasons why politicians often turn to the organized party in search for a sustainable way to solve these problems and thus be more likely to achieve these goals.

    Ambitious politicians turn to the political party to achieve such goals only when parties are useful vehicles for solving problems that cannot be solved as effectively, if at all, through other means. Thus I believe that the political party must be understood not only in relation to the goals of the actors most consequential for parties, but also in relation to the electoral, legislative, and executive institutions of the government. Fiorina was correct: only given our institutions can we understand political parties.

    The third major force shaping the political party is the historical setting. Technological changes, for instance, have made campaigning for office today vastly different than it was only a few decades ago, let alone in the nineteenth century. Such changes have had great consequences for political parties. In the nineteenth century, political parties were the only feasible means for organizing mass elections. Today’s technologies allow an individual member of Congress to create a personal, continuing campaign organization, something that was simply unimaginable a century ago. But there is, of course, more to the historical context than technology.

    Normative understandings have changed greatly. Even Ronald Reagan, who claimed that "government is not the solution to our problems, government is the problem, also held to the value of a social safety net provided by the government that is far larger than even the most progressive politician of the nineteenth century could have imagined. Ideas, in short, matter a great deal. Founders had to overcome antipathy verging on disgust over the very idea of political parties in order to create them in the first place, and Martin Van Buren’s ideas about the nature and value of the modern mass party" greatly shaped the nature of Jacksonian Democracy and political parties generally for more than a century. Neither Van Buren nor anyone else set out to create a system of competing mass parties (although he and others of that era recognized the importance of sustained partisan competition, they merely—but always—wanted to win that competiton). But the creation of the modern mass party led quickly to the creation of the first modern mass two-party system.

    History matters in yet another way, beyond the ideas, values, and technological possibilities available at any given historical moment. The path of development matters as well. Once a set of institutional arrangements is in place, the set of equilibrium possibilities is greatly reduced, and change from the existing equilibrium path to a new and possibly superior one may be difficult or impossible. In other words, once there are two major parties, their presence induces incentives for ambitious politicians to affiliate with one party or the other, and some of these incentives emerge only because of the prior existence of these two parties.

    The combination of these three forces means that the fundamental syllogism for the theory of political parties to be offered here is just what Rohde and Shepsle (1978) originally offered as the basis for the rational-choice-based new institutionalism: political outcomes—here political parties—result from actors’ seeking to realize their goals, choosing within and possibly shaping a given set of institutional arrangements, and so choosing within a given historical context.

    Before outlining this theory I provide a brief overview of the three major approaches that have long dominated the study of political parties. These prepare the way for understanding the theory of the political party, as each focuses attention on a different aspect and often on a different goal of politicians and their motivation to create or maintain a political party. I then turn to the question asked primarily in this chapter, briefly in chapter 2, and then more fully again in chapter 9 about the necessity of a system of political parties for an effective, functioning democracy. These preliminaries will provide a better sense of just what is at stake in the attempt to make sense of the major American party. Chapter 2 asks the most fundamental theoretical question: why are there parties? This discussion introduces three major theoretical problems that I believe have guided ambitious politicians as they have created, reformed, used, or ignored political parties. Part 2 puts the three major theoretical claims to test. Chapter 3 examines the origins of the first two political parties in the 1790s, emerging out of the legislative arena, attempting to solve a fundamental problem of social choice, and completing ratification by deciding just how strong and active the new national government was to be. Chapter 4 looks at the formation of the modern mass political party by focusing on its hallmark, the mobilization of the electorate—perhaps the most evident example of collective action and its inherent problems. Chapter 5 examines the other side of the Democratic and Whig parties of this period, the complex institutional arrangements these two parties helped shape that effectively kept the slavery issue off the agenda, making the union viable into the 1850s. That chapter then turns to the breakup of that party system and the rise of the Republican Party, looking especially at the interplay between the career goals of ambitious politicians and the slavery issue that culminated in the Civil War. The three chapters in part 2 conveniently illustrate the three theoretical problems that parties have been employed to attack (when it has been in the interests of politicians to use the parties), cover the formative period of political parties ending with the establishment of competition between Democrats and Republicans, and establish the form of parties and the basic nature of the historical path that survived, albeit with many important changes, through the post–World War II era.

    Part 3 turns to the modern era. In this section I analyze the contemporary scene generally but look especially at the changes wrought in elections, governance, and hence parties in the 1960s. It was this set of changes that set in motion the empirical patterns that some saw as the decline (dealignment, decay, even decomposition) of parties but culminated in the rise of polarized parties. Chapter 6 examines the party-in-elections. Chapter 7 develops the theory of the party-in-government, in light of the electoral forces. Chapter 8 looks at the oft-ignored party-as-organization and the new form of party I argue emerged in response to the politics of the 1960s and 1970s. The lacuna that many noted as the decline of parties was not, by this account, so much simply decline as the change from what I call the party in control of its ambitious office seekers and holders to the party in service to them. Chapter 9 concludes by reexamining the historical dynamics of the post–World War II era and considers the role of a party system in American democracy.

    PREVIOUS APPROACHES TO THE STUDY OF AMERICAN POLITICAL PARTIES

    Parties as Diverse Coalitions, Aggregating and Articulating the Interest in and of the Public

    There are three basic views or understandings of major political parties in America.³ The first is most often associated with V. O. Key Jr. (e.g., 1964), Frank Sorauf (1964; now Hershey 2009), Samuel Eldersveld (1964, 1982), and others. The major American party, to them, is a broad and encompassing organization, a coalition of many and diverse partners, that is commonly called umbrella-like. In seeking to appeal to a majority of the public, the two parties are based on similar values, roughly defining the American creed. McClosky (1969) said of political (which is to say partisan) elites, The evidence suggests that it is the [political elites] rather than the public who serve as the major repositories of the public conscience and as the carriers of the Creed. Responsibility for keeping the system going, hence, falls most heavily upon them (286). His basic finding was that such elites share most elements of this creed.

    On many policy issues, however, there are clear and sometimes sharply drawn lines between the two parties. What Benjamin I. Page (1978) referred to as partisan cleavages are possible, even likely. On civil rights, as on many other issues, the Democratic Party has been more liberal than the Republican Party for decades, and on New Deal economic issues even a generation longer. In chapter 6 we will see a great deal of evidence that Democratic officeholders and activists are, in fact, more liberal than comparable Republicans on many issues and that the public perceives those differences (see table 6.1). The line of cleavage now is especially sharp, but it has been clearly discernible for a long time, even when parties were at their most diverse.

    On other issues the line is less sharp and at times all but invisible. Even in this era of resurgent polarization between the two parties, many (and often most) roll call votes are not partisan. Survey researchers rarely choose to ask about issues that do not divide parties, but table 6.1 illustrates several policies on which the two parties are less clearly distinguished. Although both parties value democratic principles, the free market, equal opportunity, and the like, and though both adhere to the principles of a strong economy, peace maintained by a defense adequate for that purpose, and so on, they differ in the relative emphasis they place on such values, and they differ even more in the means or policies they consider appropriate for achieving those ends. Thus the Democrats are more likely to favor the active intervention of the government, especially the national government, on economic and social welfare issues, whereas the Republicans are much less so inclined. Democrats have long appealed to the poor, the working class, and Franklin Roosevelt’s common man. Republicans have sought support from the middle class and up, suburbanites, and the burgeoning Sun Belt.

    With few exceptions these distinctions between the two major parties are tendencies, not certainties, and differing values are typically matters of emphasis rather than fundamental disagreements. As a consequence, with the exception of race, socioeconomic groups divide their votes broadly between the candidates of both parties. As Abramson, Aldrich, and Rohde report (2010, 128–29, table 5-2), excepting only race, the proportions of major socioeconomic groups voting for one presidential nominee compared with the other rarely reached or exceeded a difference of twenty percentage points from 1952 through 2008. Thus, in a close election, a group that split its vote by as much as, say, 60–40 would be understood as giving a very large vote for one party, but the disadvantaged party nonetheless would be supported by a substantial minority of that group.

    Each party is a coalition of many and diverse groups. This is most evident in the New Deal coalition Roosevelt forged in creating a working Democratic majority in the 1930s. It consisted of the then-solid South, cities, immigrants, blacks, ethnic and religious groups of many types, the working class and unions, and so on. Over half a century later this coalition of minorities has frayed considerably; some parts of it have exited from the coalition entirely, and the remnants are no longer capable of reaching majority size in presidential elections. Although some elements have left entirely or their loyalties have weakened, they have been replaced by others. For example, the Democratic coalition may no longer be home to as much of the South or as many blue-collar voters, but teachers’ unions, women’s groups, and organizations representing blacks, Hispanics, gays, environmentalists, and many others have been added since the 1960s to the panoply of voices seeking to be heard at their national convention. The Republican Party may once have been defined more easily by what wasn’t included in the New Deal coalition, but it too has attracted a range of groups and interests. At Republican conventions one can find both Wall Street and Main Street fiscal conservatives, and westerners who seek to remove government interference in their lives (and lands), but also southerners who are social conservatives, the latter including pro-life groups, fundamentalist Christians, and so on, who seek active government intervention in behalf of their central concerns.

    Although there are good reasons why these groups are allied with their particular parties, there is still great diversity within each party. There are even apparent contradictions latent—and at critical moments active—within each party. Blacks and white southerners may have found alliance comfortable when both were so deeply affected by the Great Depression, but when civil rights made it onto the national agenda in the 1950s and 1960s, the latent tensions in their respective views become active and divisive. Recent Republican conventions may have been noncontroversial, but fundamentalists and Wall Street business leaders, or other pairings, may well find that latent disagreements will become just as divisive when circumstances and the political agenda change. As of this writing, tea party and other conservative activists are engaging the Republican regulars on many such fronts.

    In this view James Madison was correct. There is no small set of fixed interests; there are, rather, many and diverse interests in this extended Republic. He argued that a fundamental advantage of the new Constitution in creating a stronger federation was that the most evident and serious concern about majority rule—that a cohesive majority could tyrannize any minority—would be alleviated because there could be no cohesive majority in an extended republic. So too could no political party, no matter how large, rule tyrannically, because it must also be too diverse.

    In a truly diverse republic, the problem is the opposite of majority tyranny. The problem is how to form any majority capable of taking action to solve pressing problems. A major political party aggregates these many and varied interests sufficiently to appeal to enough voters to form a majority in elections and to forge partisan-based, majority coalitions in government. In this view, parties are intermediaries that connect the public and the government. Parties also aggregate these diverse interests into a relatively cohesive, if typically compromise, platform,⁵ and they articulate these varied interests by representing them in government. The result, in this view, is that parties parlay those compromise positions into policy outcomes, and so they—a ruling, if nonhomogeneous and shifting, government majority—can be held accountable to the public in subsequent elections.

    The diversity of interests a party must seek to aggregate and the diversity of actors in the party lead to an equally diverse set of party arrangements. Key’s (1964) and Sorauf’s (1964; Hershey 2009) long influential texts, for example, have presented the political party as divided into three parts: the party-in-the-electorate, the party-in-government, and the party-as-organization, meant to provide some coherence for understanding the wide variety of activities parties must engage in. These diverse structures make possible the key concepts of the party in this view: interest articulation and aggregation and electoral accountability (see Eldersveld 1964).

    The Responsible Party Thesis

    If the first view of interest aggregation and articulation was primarily empirical but with normative overtones (if parties are a major way by which the public interacts with and shapes its government, then that must be a good thing, right?), the second view, that of responsible parties, is primarily normative and aspirational, with critique of the empirics of party politics thrown in. This thesis is most directly associated with E. E. Schattschneider (1942) and the Committee for a More Responsible Two-Party System, sponsored by the American Political Science Association, that he chaired (1950). But this view has deeper historical roots. Woodrow Wilson’s Congressional Government (1881), for example, included a plea for parties more in the responsible party mold, and as Ranney (1975) and Epstein (1986) report, prominent political scientists at the beginning of the twentieth century were much enamored of this doctrine.

    Ranney (1975, 43) lists four criteria that define responsible parties. Such parties (1) make policy commitments to the electorate, (2) are willing and able to carry them out when in office, (3) develop alternatives to government policies when out of office, and (4) differ sufficiently between themselves to provide the electorate with a proper range of choice between alternative actions.⁶ This doctrine derives from an idealized (and more closely realized) form of the British system, what Lijphart (1984, 1999) calls the Westminster model. As a normative standard, it has several obvious defects. For example, it reduces choices for the public to exactly two. If the United States is a diverse and extended Madisonian republic, it is not obvious that the public would find its views adequately articulated by exactly two options, no matter how clear and distinct. A mélange of compromise proposals may be more suitable. Alternation of parties in office may also make policy trajectories shift dramatically back and forth. And if one party does capture a longtime working majority, majority tyranny could follow. This is a normative standard that thus places great weight on the accountability of elected officials, through their party’s control of office, and less weight on interest articulation. In more practical terms, it is an idealization that fits more readily with a unified, essentially unicameral assembly that combines the legislative and executive branches and that is elected all at once. It fits more poorly with a government designed around the principles of separated but intermingled powers, with offi-cials elected at different times from differently defined constituencies for the Madisonian purpose of making ambition check ambition.

    Notwithstanding these problems, the responsible party thesis retains its attractiveness to many. In the 1970s, when parties seemed in more serious decline than usual, electoral accountability was seen as not just weakened but virtually nonexistent (e.g., Fiorina 1980). Such pressing problems as the budget deficit could not be solved because of too-weak and nonresponsible parties—as contrasted to today, where budget deficits are seen as insoluble because of too-strong and nonresponsible parties. Campaigns seemed to turn on the trivial, the personal, and the irrelevant, leaving debate—let alone action—on significant problems off the agenda. Finally, the public perceived the government as increasingly ineffective and incompetent. Cynicism was up, trust and confidence in the government were down. Alienation increasesd, participation decreased (see Abramson 1983; Lipset and Schneider 1987). And the public came to see the political parties as increasingly irrelevant to elections and to governance (see Wattenberg 1990; this volume, chap. 6). When the parties’ candidates did address issues, it is often felt, they were too similar. Conservative Republicans in the 1940s and 1950s complained that the dominant, moderate wing of their party engaged in me-too-ism; whatever Democrats said, the moderate Republicans responded me too! Or as George Wallace, the once and future Democrat, claimed in his third-party presidential campaign in 1968, there ain’t a dime’s worth of difference between the two parties. It was not always so, responsible party advocates claimed. In other eras parties were stronger, and they were stronger in the sense of responsible parties. At the very least they were sufficiently united in office to be willing and able to carry out whatever policy commitments the majority party chose. They may not have been then, and today may not truly be, responsible parties, consistent with that doctrine, but they once were stronger, more effective, and more easily held accountable. Perhaps they could become so again.

    The advocates had a point. In much of our partisan history, American parties were stronger than when Schattschneider, Ranney, et al., were writing. The Republicans and Democrats have competed nationwide since the end of Reconstruction. Beginning in the late 1930s, these two parties began parallel declines, at least by some measures such as the level of party voting in Congress (see chap. 7), bottoming out in the early 1970s. Both then started to climb back toward what now appear to be the historically more common levels of partisan polarization. It so happens, by this account, that the 1950s and 1960s were the historical anomaly, and part of the anomalous and unique nature of this period was that it was far from fulfilling Ranney’s four conditions.

    And, from a normative perspective, if my claim is correct that a party system is necessary for effective democracy, the major but partial defect in our democratic system was coming home to roost. That defect was the systematic violation of the principles of democratic competition in the South. This had long been a problem, of course, but the elevation of concerns about those systematically excluded by presumptively unconstitutional law and by force was moving up onto the national agenda. As a result, the weakness of one-third of the nation’s failure to be democratic was being revealed, in large part, through its party system.

    The previous paragraphs illustrated a number of the concerns raised by the decline of parties thesis, and that thesis often has some version of responsible parties as the standard for measuring the extent of the claimed decline. Not all agreed that the parties had declined—at least as much as, or in the same sense as, was held by the major adherents of decline. One characteristic of the older, stronger party periods was that large regions of the country were dominated by a single party. The South was solidly Democratic for a century, machines ruled in many cities and in some rural areas, and in such areas of one-party dominance there was for long periods effectively no competition for office by the opposing party. Thus articulation, aggregation, and accountability were all lost. Today both parties can seriously imagine competing effectively—and possibly winning—in every region of the nation.⁷ And genuine competition for elective office has long been claimed as one of the most important virtues of political parties. As Hofstadter argued (1969), the legitimation of opposition made possible the success of the young Republic, solving perhaps the greatest internal threat to any nation by making possible the peaceful, legitimate transfer of power. The emergence of the Federalist and Jeffersonian Republican Parties made legitimation of opposition possible and effected such a transfer in 1800 (see chap. 3). The absence of regular—and that means partisan—competition for elective office, moreover, risks tyranny or corruption (that is the simplest statement of Key’s argument [1949], which I expand upon below and in chap. 9).

    Parties and Electoral Competition

    The third view of parties focuses on the importance of this competition for office. Of course both earlier views also saw electoral competition as a central characteristic of partisan politics. But this third view sees competition for office as the singular, defining characteristic of the major American political party. The most rigorous advocates of this position are Anthony Downs (1957) and Joseph A. Schlesinger (1991; see also Demsetz 1990). Both are rational choice theorists, positing that actors are goal seekers and that their actions, and eventually the institutional arrangements they help shape, are the product of their attempts to realize their goals. At the center of their theory are the partisan elites: the aspiring office seekers and the successful officeholders. Their theories rest, moreover, on a simple assumption about the goal of each such partisan elite, office seeking and holding per se. That is, party leaders are motivated to win elections. As a result a party is, in the words of Downs (1957, 25), a team seeking to control the governing apparatus by gaining office in a duly constituted election. The political party therefore is the organization that team uses to realize its goals. Electoral victory is paramount; other motives are at most secondary. Most important, as Downs puts it, parties formulate policies to win elections rather than winning elections to promulgate policies. In a two-party system, the health of the system is measured by how competitive the two parties are for a wide range of elective offices over a long period. In Schlesinger’s view (1991), the hallmark of a party is its ability to channel the competing career ambitions of its potential and actual officeholders, forming them into an effective electoral machine. More accurately, he argued that each office and its partisan seeker serves as one nucleus of a party, and a strong party is one that has many strong nuclei connected to each other for the purpose of supporting its ambitious partisan office seekers.

    The genius of democracy, in this view, is rather like the genius Adam Smith found in the free market. In Smith’s case individuals acting in their own self-interest turn out to be guided, as if by some unseen hand, to act in the economic interests of the collective. In Schlesinger’s case ambitious politicians, seeking to have a long and successful career, are all led by the necessity of winning broad support in the face of stiff competition to reflect the desires of those citizens who support them. Without competition for office—without at least minimally strong political parties—career ambition is not necessarily harnessed to reflect the desires of the public. In elections, political parties serve the Madisonian principle of having ambition clash with, and thereby check, ambition. Seeking popular support in the face of competition yields officeholders who find it in their self-interest to respond to the wishes of the public so that that public will continually reelect them, thereby satisfying their career ambition. All else about parties flows from this Schumpeterian view. Office seekers will try to create a strong electoral machine for mobilizing the electorate, but only if competition forces them to do so. Thus will the party-as-organization flow from competition for office. So too will the party-in-government flow naturally from electoral competition—but only so long as it is in the long-term career interests of office seekers and holders to do so. Only so long, that is, as there is a shared, collective interest in working together in office, and doing so to remain in office.⁸ And that collective interest must come from a common electoral fate.

    These, then, are the three major views or understandings of political parties. I will offer a fourth. Like those of Downs and Schlesinger, it will be a rational choice theory, and it will be one that takes career ambitions of elective office seekers and holders as one of its central building blocks. It will differ, however, in seeing office seeking as only one of several goals held by those with political ambitions. To be sure, winning elections is an intermediary end on its way to achieving power and policy in addition to being an end in itself. Motivations for policy ends and for power and prestige in office, that is, require electoral victory. But for many, winning office per se is not the end of politics but the beginning. As we will see, this leads naturally and inevitably to drawing from the other views of parties, and it will be necessary to trace the historical, equilibrium path of development. My aim is also to develop a theoretical account of parties that can help us make sense of the widest possible array of empirical findings relevant to party politics. Understanding the nature of the political party, however, takes us only part of the way to understanding the party’s role in democracy. For parties are engendered by but also reflect back on democratic politics. But it is not any one party alone that can achieve that reflection. Indeed, democracy fails when there is but one party. Instead it is necessary to have a party system, an ongoing competition between two or more durable parties.

    A THEORY OF POLITICAL PARTIES

    These and other astute observers might come to very different conclusions, but they all agree that the political party is—or should be—central to the American political system. Parties are—or should be—integral parts of all political life, from structuring the reasoning and choice of the electorate, through all facets of campaigns and seemingly all facets of the government, to the very possibility of effective governance in a democracy.

    How is it, then, that such astute observers of American politics and parties, writing at virtually the same time in the 1970s and 1980s and looking at much the same evidence, come to such diametrically opposed conclusions about the strength of parties? Eldersveld provided an obvious answer. He wrote that political parties are complex institutions and processes, and as such they are difficult to understand and evaluate (1982, 407). As proof, he went on to consider the decline of parties thesis. At one point he wrote, The decline in our parties, therefore, is difficult to demonstrate, empirically or in terms of historical perspective (417). And yet he then turned to signs of party decline and concluded his book with this statement: Despite their defects they continue today to be the major instruments for democratic government in this nation. With necessary reforms we can make them even more central to the governmental process and to the lives of American citizens. Eighty years ago, Lord James Bryce, after studying our party system, said, ‘In America the great moving forces are the parties. The government counts for less than in Europe, the parties count for more. . . .’ If our citizens and their leaders wish it, American parties will still be the ‘great moving forces’ of our system (1982,

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1