Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

The Ecosystem Approach: Complexity, Uncertainty, and Managing for Sustainability
The Ecosystem Approach: Complexity, Uncertainty, and Managing for Sustainability
The Ecosystem Approach: Complexity, Uncertainty, and Managing for Sustainability
Ebook683 pages8 hours

The Ecosystem Approach: Complexity, Uncertainty, and Managing for Sustainability

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Is sustainable development a workable solution for today's environmental problems? Is it scientifically defensible? Best known for applying ecological theory to the engineering problems of everyday life, the late scholar James J. Kay was a leader in the study of social and ecological complexity and the thermodynamics of ecosystems. Drawing from his immensely important work, as well as the research of his students and colleagues, The Ecosystem Approach is a guide to the aspects of complex systems theories relevant to social-ecological management.



Advancing a methodology that is rooted in good theory and practice, this book features case studies conducted in the Arctic and Africa, in Canada and Kathmandu, and in the Peruvian Amazon, Chesapeake Bay, and Chennai, India. Applying a systems approach to concrete environmental issues, this volume is geared toward scientists, engineers, and sustainable development scholars and practitioners who are attuned to the ideas of the Resilience Alliance-an international group of scientists who take a more holistic view of ecology and environmental problem-solving. Chapters cover the origins and rebirth of the ecosystem approach in ecology; the bridging of science and values; the challenge of governance in complex systems; systemic and participatory approaches to management; and the place for cultural diversity in the quest for global sustainability.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateSep 29, 2008
ISBN9780231507202
The Ecosystem Approach: Complexity, Uncertainty, and Managing for Sustainability
Author

David Waltner-Toews

David Waltner-Toews is an internationally celebrated veterinary epidemiologist, eco-health,  and One Health specialist. He has published more than 20 books of fiction, nonfiction, and poetry

Read more from David Waltner Toews

Related to The Ecosystem Approach

Related ebooks

Environmental Science For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for The Ecosystem Approach

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    The Ecosystem Approach - David Waltner-Toews

    A Preface

    David Waltner-Toews, Nina-Marie E. Lister, and Stephen Bocking

    The universe we live in is confusing, complex, and sometimes opaque to our queries of it. As scientists, we simplify it to try to understand it. Systems thinking is one approach to simplification that has proven useful for answering certain sets of questions. The ecosystem approach as described in this book is an attempt to bring together an ecological understanding of the world with a desire to make the world a convivial place for our species.

    The distinction between social systems and ecological systems, and the linking of them into social-ecological systems, is a useful simplification for teasing apart difficult problems. Insofar as our species interacts with other species and the landscapes we live in, we are ecological beings; insofar as we consume and excrete nutrients and use energy, we are members of ecosystems. An urban landscape is certainly a social system. It is also as much an ecosystem as any rural landscape or wilderness. Just as the restructuring of landscapes by cattle, elephants, or coral do not change scientific abilities to describe those landscapes in ecosystemic terms, just so urban restructuring by people does not change the essential ecological nature of a city.

    Pandemics of avian influenza and salmonellosis reflect the sad fact that the ecological nature of urban settlements is often forgotten or neglected. This neglect results in outbreaks, epidemics, and pandemics caused by infectious agents that take advantage of various feedback loops in the ecosystems we inhabit. For instance, there is evidence that the pandemic of human disease with Salmonella enteritidis in the 1980s and 1990s was attributable to eradication of the poultry pathogen Salmonella pullorum (the cause of fowl plague) from commercial chickens (Rabsch et al. 2000).

    This pandemic (like that of avian influenza) can be understood as a function of social systems, ecological systems, linked social-ecological systems, and fully integrated socioecological or ecosocial systems. Each of these systemic constructions is useful for answering a different set of questions.

    For the poultry industry, the Salmonella pandemic can be usefully explored as a function of a social system constructed to feed urban populations. Biologists can learn a great deal about ecological roles and the global circulation and adaptation of microbial populations by looking at the pandemic as a function of an ecological system. Linking the social and ecological systems yields useful insights into policy alternatives that might satisfy several conflicting criteria related to keeping down consumer prices and preventing foodborne diseases. Finally, by considering the interactions between different species of mammals, birds, and bacteria, using different criteria (organism, animal, flock; individual, population) at different scales (microscopic, bioregional, global), one can begin to ask questions related to the sustainability of different efforts to promote global human health and nutrition.

    The elements that an investigator chooses to put into a particular systemic model also reflect the questions being asked. These might include the molecular structure of a microbe, its genetic history, eating habits of various urban consumers (which reflect in part cultural histories), shedding rates of different bacteria by chickens under different housing conditions, and patterns of global trade.

    It is the premise of the work in this book that the reality humanity inhabits can only be known through our perceptual organs (primarily, the eyes and ears) and their technological extensions. We are inside the world and have evolved within it. We have no external observer to tell us when we have got it right. Scientific disciplines have generally been defined, and have made progress, by narrowing the field of permissible questions and agreeing on sets of rules that enable the group to answer those questions. For scientists that work in this philosophical tradition, which some have termed reductionist, other questions, other modes of inquiry, and other criteria for quality are often marginalized and sometimes denigrated.

    The epidemiological literature, for instance, is rife with aspersions on ecological studies, which are seen as being primarily case studies and which are dismissed as the weakest form of study possible. The ecological fallacy—drawing conclusions about individuals based on studies of groups—is spoken of with a certain level of derision in the epidemiological literature. This pejorative use of ecological has arisen because epidemiologists have wanted to define risk factors for diseases in individuals that are universally true. What would be the point of a study that could only conclude that smoking caused lung cancer in one subset of individuals living in an area of Nepal, with a particular ecological and social history? Hence epidemiological studies have focused on large populations and relatively stable traits. These studies have been most successful at identifying genetic markers, toxic exposures, and individual behaviors that result in disease. They have been much less successful in determining relationships between human disease and changes in social and ecological systems. Most post-World War II epidemiological investigations have been deliberately designed to exclude these kinds of variables.

    Acceptance of a wider range of modes of inquiry and criteria for evaluation of results has only recently changed when some epidemiologists decided to ask different kinds of questions, particularly with respect to relationships between human well being and global environmental and climate change. Similar changes have occurred in a subset of those scholars asking related questions related to environmental management. By collectively pooling our perceptions and openly challenging them according to multiple, agreed upon criteria, we, as a species, are likely to be more successful in solving the difficult problems of global sustain-ability than if we fall back into mutually exclusive paradigms. As the Millennium Ecosystem Assessment made clear, answering questions about how to manage for sustainability incorporates both science as we have come to know it and pushes its boundaries into realms of policy and philosophy.

    According to Funtowicz and Ravetz (chapter 17), these new problems can be characterized by situations where the facts are uncertain, values are in dispute, the decision-making stakes are high, and there is a sense of urgency that decisions be made. In these situations, they have suggested that normal paradigm-driven science (in the Kuhnian sense) is insufficient and that there is a need to accommodate a much wider range of modes of constructing knowledge about the world. In this setting, paradigms do not replace each other. By expanding the peer group, they play off against each other to give us a richer understanding of the world. Funtowicz and Ravetz have called this post-normal science. Post-normal scientific inquiry, in their view, is an act of collaborative learning and knowledge integration. Expertise is collective, and the role of this expertise shifts from giving correct advice to sharing information about options and trade-offs. Reductionist forms of inquiry are not marginalized but drawn upon and embraced to inform approaches that are not so much holistic as they are transdisciplinary and comprehensive. Contradictory evidence and uncertainty from complex reality is not set aside, excused, or used as an excuse to privilege some information over others but rather is incorporated into a richer, albeit less predictive, understanding.

    The theoretical constructs and the case studies from around the world that are presented in this book represent attempts to elaborate on such a science and to explore the ways in which a variety of systems constructions can be used to inform post-normal scientific inquiry.

    Since the 1980s, the sustainable management of environments, societies, and economies has become the broadly accepted backdrop for policy and management decisions in most parts of the world. For many, this backdrop provides reassuring scenery against which we play out our daily lives and think about the future. The hard fact is, however, that in all regions of the planet (individually, collectively, nationally, regionally, and globally), people are having to make urgent and controversial decisions on public health, environmental, economic development, and agricultural issues with very little scholarly or practical guidance on how to integrate multiple perspectives across spatial and temporal scales. These decisions are made even more difficult by the fact that sustainability itself, being the capacity to create, test, and maintain adaptive capacity over time (Gunderson and Holling 2002), requires us to reconcile ecological, economic, and social imperatives (Dale 2001). Given the scholarly and policy interest in questions that link social and ecological activities, it should not be surprising that some of the key insights into how to structure inquiries to answer these questions should have come from ecologists and environmental managers.

    The issues of this work of reconciliation are complex and interacting, where the decision-making stakes, the scientific uncertainty, and the conflicts over what constitutes legitimate knowledge are high. Even as we speak of managing for global sustainability, we are faced with ethical imperative to deal with ethnic pluralism, multiple epistemologies, and place-based biodiversity. Scientists are often at loggerheads over how to advise politicians and the public, quarrelling about data and their interpretation in front of television cameras. Having grown accustomed to a way of doing science that breaks out the pieces and gives them to experts, we are faced with making decisions that demand integrated and integrative answers, where the collective expertise is an emergent property of many different modes of inquiry. Furthermore, as Berkes and Davidson-Hunt (chapter 7) point out, we are increasingly aware that if an ecosystem is not an object to be understood or managed by external agents, but a place of dwelling for a group of people who use it, then what are the implications of this for research and management?

    Indeed, after all the rhetoric of global conferences, we might ask, is managing for sustainability possible? If so, how? Without good theory, good management can only happen by accident. Without practice, all theories are suspect. Are there ways to combine science and management in a way that builds on the strengths of both? Can we learn our way into a sustainable (human) future on this planet? These issues cut across all areas of practice—including health, urban planning, natural resource conservation, agriculture, international development—and a wide variety of areas of scholarly inquiry.

    The ecosystems we call home are diverse, complex, and dynamic. As a species, we have at once accelerated the speed and increased the scale of changes that were already nonlinear and full of surprises. As such, there is considerable scientific uncertainty surrounding ecosystem change and the management of human activities. The high degree of uncertainty, coupled with an urgent need for more for sustainable development necessitates a fundamentally different and more creative approach to decision-making. Traditional (disciplinary) science, while necessary, is not by itself sufficient for understanding and dealing with ecosystems, especially if these are understood to have embedded in systems and organizations created by that peculiar species, Homo sapiens. As ecologists and environmental managers were among the first to recognize, a new, broadened, and interdisciplinary approach bridging science and management is essential.

    The history of environmental management in the twentieth-century has been described in some detail by Bocking (1997, 2004). What we describe in this book is what has emerged in the 1980s and took new forms in the 1990s and beyond. The new ecosystem approach we describe represents a synthesis between conventional ways of framing both ecological problems and environmental management and more recent theories of complex systems. This approach is not intended to displace the focused science that has been the backbone of biological inquiry for the past century but rather to embrace that work, to build on it, and to find ways to connect it to large temporal and spatial contexts.

    Beginning in the early 1970s, confidence in ecosystem ecology’s central role in ecological research and environmental policy declined. In part, this reflected the discovery that construction of realistic ecosystem models able to predict impacts of human activities is more difficult than first expected. Some also criticized the failure of ecologists and other scientists to explain their results in ways that society can comprehend. For example, early studies of climate change have been criticized for neglecting socioeconomic implications and focusing on atmospheric change to the exclusion of the economic and political variables that drive the current social-ecological system and can (perhaps) be manipulated to find solutions (Cohen et al. 1998).

    Most importantly, the political context changed. In the United States, and to some extent in Canada, the belief in comprehensive management prevalent in the late 1960s was replaced by renewed reliance on processes more typical of a pluralistic political system, such as negotiation, compromise, and brokerage of competing interests, which are often conducted in an adversarial environment. Acceptance of a positive role for government in fostering society’s interests was replaced by greater reliance on competition, private initiative, and individual interests. This implied a shift in the perceived role of science. No longer an alternative to political processes (as ecosystem ecology was once envisaged), science has instead become a participant, contributing knowledge that is useful in decision-making and dispute resolution and that is considered factual and value neutral. In this way, science was seen to impart an air of objectivity to the resulting decision (Bocking 2004; Jasanoff 1989; Nelkin 1992). Such a role placed a premium on quantifiable, precise predictions, which ecosystem ecologists were not immediately able to provide.

    Although ecosystem ecology in its old, purely biophysical sense suffered a period of eclipse in this new political landscape, a variety of vigorous alternative views of ecosystems developed to take into account the rapidly changing nature of scientific inquiry and its role in society. Those who claimed ecosystems studies had disappeared were perhaps looking in the wrong places. New insights from fields as disparate as ecosystem studies, general systems theory, cybernetics, soft systems methodology, complex systems theories, hierarchy theory, thermodynamics, and chaos theory have brought together in new ways of understanding both ecosystems and our roles in them. Many of these new insights emerged from the work of scholars, such as Henry Regier, George Francis, Thomas Hoekstra, and Tim Allen, who were active in the scientific activities of International Joint Commission of the Great Lakes from the 1970s onward, as well as the Resilience Alliance of Holling and Gunderson. From these insights into the complex interactions within what now can only be viewed as hybrids of social and ecological systems (there being no pristine, nonhuman-influenced systems extant) have emerged new concepts of management and, indeed, new ways of thinking about science. These have, in turn, led to the notions of post-normal science and emergent complexity. The ecosystem approach as described in this book reflects those new ways of thinking. Some of the pioneers in ecosystem studies might have difficulty recognizing the intellectual world inhabited by the ecosystem approach as described in this book, as they would no doubt have difficulty recognizing the biophysical and social world we now inhabit. Yet these new ways of thinking about our interactions with the natural world are deeply indebted to these pioneers and their ideas.

    Scientific concepts rarely reflect simply an objective understanding of empirical reality. As the history of the ecosystem approach suggests, their evolution reflects not only our changing understanding of nature but our evolving sense of the role of science, and ultimately, of our place in the world. In describing nature, we describe ourselves. Since the 1930s, our understanding of ecosystems has been shaped not only by empirical observations but also by ecologists’ changing visions of their discipline, of their place within society, and of the shared intellectual and cultural landscape we inhabit. The broader acceptance of ecosystem approach has been conditioned not only by empirical evidence or theoretical rigor, nor even by the reinvention of ecosystems studies themselves as described in this book, but also by how society views itself and the roles of individuals and institutions within it. By understanding this interdependence of ideas of nature, science, and society, we can better understand how the ecosystem approach can address the challenge of fostering respect for, and nurturing the sustainability of, the ecosystems that are our home.

    This book presents an emerging integrative and innovative approach to managing for sustainability, not only in the midst of uncertainty and complexity but also in the midst of political, economic, and ecological turmoil. Integrating complex systems theories and participatory (and in some cases, collaborative) management, the ecosystem approach as we describe it in this book has grown out of, and feeds back into, case studies from around the world, ranging geographically from Canada and New Zealand to India, Latin America and Africa, and in focus from urban and community planning, and public health, to agriculture and management of natural areas.

    All the authors represented in this book are struggling to find integrative and innovative solutions to the practical and theoretical challenges of understanding and nurturing sustainable, convivial, and just ways of living on this planet. Although the work of the late James Kay, which comprises a large part of the first section, informed much of the work, the relationships between the case studies and the theoretical ideas put forward by Kay were a kind of conversation and a debate. Rather than being illustrations of Kay’s frameworks, they are perhaps best seen as arguments with it, from which all of us learned, and moved on to new place-based experiments. James Kay’s untimely departure in 2004 left a large silent space in the argument around this scholarly table. We welcome our readers to engage in this discussion and to carry it to the streets and alleys, the mountain valleys and the swamps—wherever people live—and to join us in the daunting and exciting task of learning our collective way into a sustainable and convivial future.

    References

    Bocking, S. 1997. Ecologists and Environmental Politics: A History of Contemporary Ecology. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.

    Bocking, S. 2004. Nature’s Experts: Science, Politics, and the Environment. New Brunswick, N. J.: Rutgers University Press.

    Cohen, S., D. Demeritt, J. Robinson and D. Rothman. 1998. Climate change and sustainable development: Towards dialogue. Global Environmental Change 8(4):341–371.

    Dale, A. 2001. At the Edge: Sustainable Development in the 21st Century. Vancouver, Canada: University of British Columbia Press.

    Gunderson, L. H. and C. S. Holling (eds.). 2002. Panarchy: Understanding Transformations in Human and Natural Systems. Washington, D. C.: Island Press.

    Jasanoff, S. 1989. The problem of rationality in American health and safety regulation. In Expert Evidence: Interpreting Science in the Law, eds. R. Smith and B. Wynne, 151–183. London, UK: Routledge.

    Nelkin, D. (ed.). 1992. Controversy: The Politics of Technical Decisions (3rd ed.). Newbury Park, Calif.: Sage.

    Rabsch, W., B. Hargis, R. Tsolis, R. Kingsely, K-H. Hinz, H. Tschäpe and A. Bäumler. 2000. Competitive exclusion of Salmonella enteritidis by Salmonella gallinarum in poultry. Emerging Infectious Diseases 6(5):443–448.

    PART I

    Some Theoretical Bases for a New Ecosystem Approach

    In this section (chapters 1–9), we cover the main theoretical and practical challenges of an ecosystem approach to managing for sustainability and some important possible responses, particularly as reflected in the ideas of the late James Kay and a few close colleagues. The intent of this section is not to provide an in-depth review of complex systems thinking but rather to identify those features that are deemed most important for the implementation of a reasonable scholarly and management response to the complexity of the world. Chapter 1 provides a basis for the more applied chapters that follow and that serve as a kind of argument, or conversation, with the theories as posited in Part I.

    1

    An Introduction to Systems Thinking

    James J. Kay
    The Nature of the Beast

    Environmental issues and sustainability have thwarted our society’s scientific approach to dealing with the world. One need only contemplate global climate change to experience the frustration and confusion. In this book, we are using the term complexity as a concept that covers problematic situations that have eluded traditional scientific solutions. Complex situations involve uncertainty and surprise. They give the impression that there is no right way of looking at them and no right answer to the problems they raise. The problem is really the singularity of our concept of the right answer. Complexity defies linear logic as it brings with it self-organization and feedback loops, wherein the effect is its own cause. Circular relationships between cause and effect require nonlinear logic, explanations in terms of morphogenetic causal loops where form is determined by and determines its own plans. In essence, complexity is characterized by situations where several different coherent future scenarios are possible, each of which may be desirable, all of which have an inherent irreducible uncertainty as to the likelihood for their actually coming about.

    The differences between the above scenarios require a number of different perspectives at different scales of investigation. Understanding complex situations thus invokes alternative perspectives, which can be perplexing. Yet there is no avoiding our environmental concerns, and so we must take up the challenge of complexity. While not a panacea, systems thinking seems to offer some insights and approaches for dealing with complexity. As such, it holds the promise of helping us chart the course to sustainability.

    Systems thinking is about patterns of relationships and how these translate into emergent behaviors. This section explores the notion of systems and its application to ecosystem thinking. Systems thinking provides us with a window on the world that informs our understanding of nature and our relationship to it. It provides us with a way of framing our investigations and a language for discussing our understanding. Translating systems thinking into action is what systems approaches are about. In this section the focus will be on systems thinking as it applies to biophysical systems.

    Making Sense of Nonlinearity: Self-Organization

    One of the puzzling observations about issues of sustainability is that everything seems to happen at once. Teasing apart causal links using conventional scientific techniques doesn’t appear to help us answer the important questions. Systems thinking can help us by providing a language and conceptual tools for talking about the richness that comes with complexity.

    Underlying systems thinking is the premise that systems behave as a whole and that such behavior cannot be explained solely in terms that simply aggregate the individual elements. This premise is, of course, the antithesis of prevalent reductionist thinking. Take, for example, evapotranspiration in a wetland. If one measures the evapotranspiration for the plants that make up the wetland when they are isolated in pots and add this to the evaporation for open pans of water (the classical experiment), one gets a higher value than the evapotranspiration of the plants and the open water when they are together in a wetland. One perspective on this is that when the plants transpire, they increase the humidity of the local atmosphere, thus decreasing the evaporation from the open water. Then again, does increased open water decrease plant evapotranspiration? The nonlinear causality in the loops typical of such systems makes distinguishing causal order impossible. Furthermore, this emergent property of wetlands cannot be deduced from more intensely studying their individual elements in isolation. Yet the dominant reductionist approaches are so entrenched that I have personally dealt with senior scholars who cannot accept that the evapotranspiration of a wetland is not simply the sum of the evapotranspiration of its component parts. There is a certain myopia in the dominant reductionist approaches, and it hinders our ability to deal with situations where emergence (i.e., the whole is more than the sum of the parts) is an important feature. Systems thinking is well suited to understanding such situations that require considerations of the whole as an emergent with its own properties.

    An important emergent property of the whole is self-organization. We shall discuss this in more detail in a later chapter. However, it is important for us to introduce the notion here because self-organization is the phenomenon that gives us a sense that a system has an identity of its own. A simple example is a school of fish or a herd of wildebeest. The school as a whole seems to move of its own accord. Understanding or modeling this movement comes from understanding the relationship that is maintained between individual fish and wildebeest rather than from independent behavior of the individual itself. Self-organization is about how coherent patterns of relationships are internally structured and develop over time. How these relationships develop over time leads to a number of surprising and counterintuitive phenomena.

    One of the manifestations of self-organization, which gives us a sense of a whole is the way in which systems deal with disturbance and, indeed, often incorporate disturbance as an important element of their dynamics. DeAngelis (1986) gives an example of this from southeastern Australia. The dominant trees are sclerophyllous eucalyptus, but the undergrowth consists of lush mesophytic vegetation. Normally, these circumstances would give rise to a temperate rain forest. However, these systems are subject to frequent fire, which would not occur if the mesophytic vegetation dominated. Fire increases soil leaching and sclerophylls are better adapted to poorer soils than mesophylls. Thus the dominance by sclerophyllous forest depends on fire and the occurrence of fire depends on the dominance by sclerophyllous forest. So fire has been incorporated as an integral element to the existence of the sclerophyllous dominant forest.

    In a sense, the self-organization is a happenstance outcome of fire and the vegetation meeting. The components of the vegetation are significantly already evolved before the components of the new stable configuration ever came together. While the organisms in the forest are coded by DNA, the self-organization supersedes all that. There may be some microevolution that causes the components to line up in detail as they stabilize the emergent vegetation type. However, as with all self-organization, it comes down to flux and process; there is no plan or script for how the situation plays out.

    This example also illustrates the importance of feedbacks and morphogenetic causal loops in understanding self-organization. In this case the feedback loop is that fires increase soil leaching, which increases the sclerophylls at the expense of the mesophylls, thus increasing the amount of forest fire. This would quickly get out of control, except that the mesophytic undergrowth limits the amount of fire, and so the whole system is in balance. It is such a balanced network of nonlinear causality that is referred to as a morphogenetic causal loop. The morphogenetic causal loop of sclerophyllous dominance, fire, and soil infertility obstructs the development of temperate rain forests and preserves the status quo.

    The nonlinear causality of such systems gets us into trouble as environmental managers. An example is forest fire in temperate forests of North America. Forests are adapted to fire and are organized in such a way that normal fires cause only small areas of damage. The fire releases nutrients and makes openings for seedlings, promoting reproduction. Normal forest fires rejuvenate forests, keep the fuel level down, and prevent larger, more damaging fires and pest outbreaks. Suppressing forest fires prevents the rejuvenation process, allows fuel to accumulate and sets the stage for conflagrations, like the one that occurred in Yellowstone in 1988. Even in hindsight, researchers remain ambivalent about the Yellowstone fire, as there was in place a management regime that encouraged fire suppression. Later research indicated that there are huge fires every 400 years or so, of which the 1988 fire may be argued as an example. Suppressing forest fires usually makes forests less healthy! Indeed, anyone who depends on linear causal models as the basis for their management decisions will find the world a perplexing place.

    Self-organizing systems have in their repertoire of behaviors a way of dealing with disturbance through their buffering capacity. In essence, one can substantially change the environmental context for such a system up to a point (a threshold or tipping point) with little apparent effect on the system. However, a slight change beyond the threshold and the system will suddenly change, that is, it reorganizes itself in a very dramatic and often unpredictable way. The effect of acid rain on lakes is an example of this phenomenon. The acidity of the precipitation running into lakes did not suddenly change; rather, it changed incrementally over decades. The pH of the lake water, however, did not change substantially, relatively speaking, over the same period (Stigliani 1988). The lakes maintained their organizational state (low pH) through a series of feedback loops that largely buffered the lake (in a chemical sense) from the environmental change. Eventually, the runoff from precipitation into the lake reached a level of acidity that exceeded the compensatory capacity of these loops. Once this happened, the effectiveness of the system decreased, which, in turn, decreased the capacity of the loops to compensate, which decreased the effectiveness of the system, and then quickly the organization unraveled and the system flipped to a different organizational state, in this case a dead acidified lake. The pH of the lakes dropped in a very short time period, less than one summer season. In some instances the change occurred in weeks.

    Again, our linear thinking can get us in trouble when we make decisions regarding such systems. When Steve Carpenter began to work with human management of lacustrine systems, he was at first surprised by the flips of behavior he saw because there are not that many examples of them in basic science applied to lake systems. However, after a series of examples in managed systems, Carpenter is now surprised if he does not find such discrete jumps in the state of the system. Carpenter et al. (1999) report this as a common phenomenon. For quite a while our interaction with the system appears not to have any (deleterious) effect. As we increase what we are doing to the system, nothing appears to happen. Then suddenly, with little warning, a small change in our behavior causes the system to change dramatically, and too late we realize that we were impacting the system. The ability of systems to buffer themselves from external influences and to incorporate external disturbance as an integral part of their patterns of organization is part of what gives us our sense of them as a whole, a whole that is adapted to the situation that it is in.

    The acid rain–lake interaction is also an example of important self-organizing phenomenon. Complex systems self-organize through feedback loops, and their openness predisposes them to dramatic reorganizations at critical points of instability (Nicolis and Prigogine 1977) (e.g., the dramatic death of an acidified lake, which is a flip to a plankton-dominated ecology). These instabilities and the resulting jumps or abrupt changes in the system are caused by self-amplified internal fluctuations mediated especially through positive feedback loops. These give rise to the spontaneous emergence of new structures and forms of behavior. Amplification is thus a source of new organization and complexity in the system. At the points at which these new structures emerge, the system may branch off into one of a number of quite different organizational states, often referred to as attractors. The existence of multiple stable states, multiple possibilities necessarily implies in-determinacy, as which path is taken depends on the system’s history and various external conditions that can never be completely predicted (Nicolis and Prigogine 1989), thus the unpredictable nature of complex systems.

    It is one thing to recognize such complexity in multiple case studies, but how do we use this information to help us make decisions about sustainability? In the 1930s, von Bertalanffy (1968) noted that open self-organizing systems exhibited common attributes regardless of the disciplinary domain of study. He called this property of systems isomorphism (Blauberg et al. 1977: chap. 2). The existence of isomorphisms allows us to make generalizations about open self-organizing systems, that is, to build a general theory about their behavior and characteristics. This is one of the premises and the impetus behind the development of von Bertalanffy’s general systems theory as well as more recent advances in systems thinking. By furnishing us with a typology and description of the patterns of relationships that can occur, both within the system and between the system and its environment, and the types of behaviors that can emerge, systems thinking provides us with a language, questions, and techniques for thinking through the self-organizing aspects of systems.

    A Brief History of Systems Theory

    The origin of the modern systems movement is generally attributed to von Bertalanffy’s work in evolutionary biology. He began his work in the 1920s, and his first major presentation was a series of lectures at the University of Chicago (1937–1938). However, his work became more widely known in the late 1940s after his arrival in Canada. His commonly known publications date back to the 1960s. Von Bertalanffy’s general systems theory was one of the first schools of thought that provided alternative models and modes of inquiry to the reductionist methods of disciplinary science. General systems thinking emphasizes connectedness, context, and feedback. Research questions identify and explain interactions, relationships, and patterns. The essential properties of the parts of a system can only be understood from the organization of the whole, as they arise from the configuration of ordered relationships that are specific to that particular system (von Bertalanffy 1968). Understanding comes from looking at how the parts operate together rather than from teasing them apart.

    The next major contribution is generally attributed to Wiener (1948), who developed the field of cybernetics. While systems thinking originated in fields associated with natural systems, those researching mechanical and human systems quickly adopted them. Early adopters of the systems ideas included Margaret Mead (see von Foerster 1952), Gerard (physiology), Rapoport (mathematical biology; Rapoport and Horvath 1959), and Boulding (1956). Churchman (1968) and Beer (1959) linked systems concepts into operations research and organizational cybernetics. In recent years, primarily through the work of Senge (1990) and Checkland (1981), systems concepts have been integrated into the management sciences.

    Complex systems thinking is the grandchild of von Bertalanffy’s general systems theory. It emerged in the wake of the new science of the 1970s: catastrophe theory, chaos theory, nonequilibrium thermodynamics and self-organization theory, Jaynesian information theory, complexity theory, etc. A number of authors have focused specifically on self-organizing systems (di Castri 1987; Jantsch 1980; Kay 1984; Nicolis and Prigogine 1977, 1989; Peacocke 1983; Wicken 1987).

    Systems theory was first developed by von Bertalanffy in response to his sense that reductionist science was not sufficient to deal with biological systems. During the Second World War the development of systems theory was spurred on by the logistics (command and control) problems of assembly, delivery, and support of large numbers of men and machines to specific locations at specific times (e.g., amphibious assaults, bomber raids). The problems of tracking multiple moving targets also motivated much thinking about cybernetics and systems organization. During this time, aircraft also began to fly so fast that human response times became a major safety issue, thus motivating the development of ergonomics. The cold war had a similar impetus on systems thinking and approaches, the problem being the organization behind the operation and control of strategic bombers and intercontinental ballistic missiles (ICBMs). Similarly, the race to the moon of the 1960s motivated the development of systems. Much of the work on systems, over the years, was carried out in the Soviet Union, and this association led to ideological issues during the Reagan years, which saw the systems movement fall into disfavor in America.

    However, with the publicity in America surrounding the Santa Fe Institute and its association with successful business management, systems thinking is once again being pursued. Currently, systems thinking is playing a major role in dealing with environmental issues, organization of global corporations, and computer networks. It is interesting to note that systems approaches have played a central role in some of the most technically and organizationally challenging activities of humans over the past half century. It is unfortunate that the impetus for the development of systems thinking and approaches has often been the problems posed by the most detestable of human activities—the waging of war. For more complete discussion of the development of systems thinking, I suggest Blauberg et al. (1977) and Flood and Jackson (1991).

    Questioning Reality from a Systems Viewpoint

    One well-known statement associated with systems thinking is that everything is connected to everything else. This is an overstatement as the connections between things can be quite weak. In the systems we study, most potential connections are set to zero. So what does the adage mean to say? It is not that everything is connected, though technically true, but rather that we should expect unsuspected and surprising connections to be important with some regularity. Because there are so many potential ways that things may surprise us, there are several dialects of systems approaches that can be useful. Systems theories, particularly those associated with nonlinearity and complexity, are not suitable for all classes of problems.

    Many problems or investigations can be completed successfully using the Newtonian worldview. Many of the discussions within the systems community focus on defining the contexts and problems best suited to the various approaches and worldviews. Weinberg (1975), following on the work of Weaver (1948), proposed the partitioning of problem situations based on their complexity and level of randomness.

    Organized (not random), simple situations, with small numbers of interactions, are designated small-number problems. Two masses orbiting each other, the trajectory of propelled objects, and simple pendulums are examples. The behavior of these entities can be explained by Newtonian science and mechanistic explanation. This is because the interactions and relationships between objects in these situations are tightly constrained and can be written as simple solvable equations.

    Highly unorganized complex situations, dominated by large numbers of random interactions and aggregate behavior, are designated large-number problems. Gas molecules in a room and large groups of people are examples. They can be adequately described by statistics and statistical mechanics. Averages mean something because there are large numbers of unconstrained (i.e., random) interactions between objects.

    The remaining middle ground, with intermediate numbers of interactions and organized complexity with only a degree of unpredictability, are designated middle-number problems. Interactions between objects are loosely constrained and in sufficient number such that averages are not helpful and equations that can be written to describe the interactions are not uniquely solvable.

    Human organizations, three masses orbiting each other, double pendulums, and ecosystems are all examples of situations where behavior cannot be explained by Newtonian mechanics or linear cause-and-effect explanations nor described in a useful way by statistical means. In middle number situations, prediction is not possible, but one can still get an answer to a slightly different question. Systems thinking is most applicable in situations where simple prediction fails. One must change the context to get an answer to the original question to one that is still useful. This idea of partitioning problem situations based on complexity, organization, and degree of constraint is key to understanding the domain of applicability of systems thinking. In middle number systems the constraints are ambiguous. As systems thinking changes the context by bounding the system in some new way, some reliable constraints come to the fore. There is a certain freedom in finding those helpful constraints, and it is the nature of the interactions between objects in a situation that determines which tools are appropriate.

    The problem is that, because normal scientific concepts work for some classes of problems, we seem to think that they must be valid for all classes of problem. We tend not to think through the connections that might lead us to a more systemic view. Environmental management projects, ranging from dams to agricultural development, have often resulted in unanticipated, usually negative, impacts. For example, large dams were seen as a panacea in development, but few thought through the ecological change they would cause. The Aswan dam on the Nile disrupted the annual flooding of the Nile, which provided the nutrients for the downstream agriculture. In order to maintain this agriculture, fertilizer has to be produced to replace the nutrients once provided by the flooding. The energy required to produce the fertilizer exceeds the energy produced by the dam, thus nullifying the energy-producing benefits of the dam. According to The World Commission on Dams (2000), many ecosystem impacts of large dams were unanticipated, even as late as the 1990s.

    In deciding whether or not we are dealing with a simple, complicated, or complex problem, we need to ask what needs to be considered and what can be ignored. How far upstream and downstream from the dam must one think about the problem? And at what level of detail? These questions combine to ask what scale of analysis is appropriate? Need we be worried about individual farms or agriculture in general? This raises one of the fundamental conundrums of systems thinking and dealing with complexity. It is a given property of systems that everything is connected (at least weakly) to everything else. However, no scientist can look at everything at once. So any analyst must make decisions about what to include and what to leave out of the system to be studied. Scale, extent, and type of study must be selected, as discussed by Allen (chapter 3). Decisions on scale and type, while done in a systematic and consistent way, are necessarily subjective, reflecting the viewpoint of the analyst about which connections are important to the study at hand and which can be ignored. So, because of their very nature, the notion of an objective scientific observer is not applicable to the study of self-organizing systems, because the new level of emergence forces changes in the decisions as to how to bound the system.

    Furthermore, this conundrum begs the question: Who gets to decide what is important and what is not? Whose values are used and why? These questions must be answered at the beginning of a system’s investigation and are clearly political in nature. The inability, in principle, to have a unique objective systems description of a situation immediately moves systems thinking and systems approaches out of the domain of traditional scientific approaches and into the realm of post-normal science. Post-normal science applies when the stakes are high, the time is short, there is much intrinsic uncertainty, and values are in conflict. Post-normal science puts front and center the issue of who gets to decide, and it develops a stagecraft for finding better, not correct, answers to that question.

    Systems thinking provides us with a heuristic tool and common language for framing situations and exploring self-organizing phenomena. It provides us with guidance about how to decide what is important to look at, and not look at, and how to describe a situation. It helps us to understand the self-organizing possibilities in a situation and thus to map out potential future scenarios. It provides a basis for synthesizing our understanding of a situation into narratives about how the future might unfold and the trade-offs that exist between choosing different paths. It also helps us understand what it is we don’t understand.

    Conclusions

    In summary, then, the complexity of problems offered by asking questions about sustainability offers a major challenge to systems thinkers. Addressing sustainability means finding a way to deal with this complexity. It has become clear that systems explanations of social-ecological complexity require different types of perspectives and at different scales of examination. There is no single correct perspective. Rather, a diversity of perspectives is required for understanding. Such systems are self-organizing; their dynamics are largely a function of positive and negative feedback loops. Linear causal mechanical explanations of dynamics are insufficient to understand them. Emergence and surprise are normal phenomena in systems dominated by feedback loops. Inherent uncertainty and limited predictability are inescapable consequences of these system phenomena. Such systems organize about attractors. Even when the environmental situation changes, the system’s feedback loops tend to maintain their current state. However, when change does occur, it can be very rapid and even catastrophic. Precisely when the change will occur and to what state the system will change are often not predictable. Frequently, in a given situation, there are several possible states (attractors) that are equivalent. Which state the system currently occupies is a function of its history. There is not a correct preferred state for the system.

    This enhanced understanding of systems, as complex systems, forms the backdrop for navigating a path to sustainability. Moving toward sustainability involves long enough timelines for the actors and the context of the ecosystem to change. These insights into buffering capacity of self-organizing phenomena address that long timeline. By contrast, the conventional science approaches of modeling and forecasting are often so inflexible as to be inappropriate, as are prevailing explanations in terms of linear causality and homeostatic properties that underpin ecosystem management of the traditional sort. The new understanding of complexity leads to an approach that is different from traditional ecosystem approaches. The conventional approaches may be interdisciplinary and participatory in nature, but they focus on analysis, forecasting, and a single type of entity such as a watershed or forest community. Complex systems approaches go beyond interdisciplinary to transdisciplinary, which invokes emergence between the disciplines over merely working between them. The new approaches

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1