Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Yale Law Journal: Volume 121, Number 6 - April 2012
Yale Law Journal: Volume 121, Number 6 - April 2012
Yale Law Journal: Volume 121, Number 6 - April 2012
Ebook601 pages11 hours

Yale Law Journal: Volume 121, Number 6 - April 2012

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

This issue of The Yale Law Journal (the 6th issue of Volume 121, academic year 2011-2012) features articles and essays by several notable scholars. Principal contributors include Daryl Levinson (on votes and rights), Michelle Wilde Anderson (on dissolving cities), and Patricia Bella (on WikiLeaks and national security law). The issue also features student contributions on elected prosecutors in legal history and on execution of the mentally retarded as an issue under section 1983 civil rights law.

The editors of The Yale Law Journal are a group of Yale Law School students, who also contribute Notes and Comments to the Journal's content. The lead articles and features are written by internationally recognized legal scholars. This is Yale Law Journal: Volume 121, Number 6 - April 2012.

LanguageEnglish
PublisherQuid Pro, LLC
Release dateApr 18, 2014
ISBN9781610279437
Yale Law Journal: Volume 121, Number 6 - April 2012
Author

Yale Law Journal

The editors of The Yale Law Journal are a group of Yale Law School students, who also contribute Notes and Comments to the Journal’s content. The principal articles are written by leading legal scholars.

Read more from Yale Law Journal

Related to Yale Law Journal

Related ebooks

Jurisprudence For You

View More

Related articles

Related categories

Reviews for Yale Law Journal

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Yale Law Journal - Yale Law Journal

    THE YALE LAW JOURNAL

    APRIL 2012

    VOLUME 121, NUMBER 6

    Yale Law School

    New Haven, Connecticut

    Yale Law Journal

    Smashwords edition. Published by Quid Pro Books at Smashwords. Copyright © 2012 by The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. All rights reserved. This work or parts of it may not be reproduced, copied or transmitted (except as permitted by sections 107 and 108 of the U.S. Copyright Law and except by reviewers for the public press), by any means including voice recordings and the copying of its digital form, without the written permission of the print publisher.

    The publisher of various editions is The Yale Law Journal, who authorized this work to be digitally published in ebook editions, for The Yale Law Journal, by Quid Pro Books. Available in major digital formats and at leading retailers and booksellers.

    Quid Pro Books

    Quid Pro, LLC

    5860 Citrus Blvd., suite D-101

    New Orleans, Louisiana 70123

    www.quidprobooks.com

    Cataloging for Volume 121, Number 6 — April 2012:

    ISBN: 1610279433 (ebk)

    ISBN-13: 978-1-61027-943-7 (ebk)

    CONTENTS

    ARTICLES

    RIGHTS AND VOTES

    By Daryl J. Levinson

    (121 YALE L.J. 1286)

    DISSOLVING CITIES

    By Michelle Wilde Anderson

    (121 YALE L.J. 1364)

    FEATURE

    WIKILEAKS AND THE INSTITUTIONAL FRAMEWORK FOR NATIONAL SECURITY DISCLOSURES

    By Patricia L. Bellia

    (121 YALE L.J. 1448)

    NOTE

    THE ORIGINS OF THE ELECTED PROSECUTOR

    By Michael J. Ellis

    (121 YALE L.J. 1528)

    COMMENT

    CAN SECTION 1983 HELP TO PREVENT THE EXECUTION OF MENTALLY RETARDED PRISONERS?

    By Doug Lieb

    (121 YALE L.J. 1571)

    About the Yale Law Journal

    RESPONSES. The Yale Law Journal invites short papers responding to scholarship appearing in the Journal within the last year. Responses should be submitted to The Yale Law Journal Online at http://yalelawjournal.org/submissions.html. We cannot guarantee that submitted responses will be published. Those responses that are selected for publication will be edited with the cooperation of the author.

    The Yale Law Journal is published eight times a year (monthly from October through June, excluding February) by The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. Editorial and general offices are located in the Sterling Law Building at Yale University. POSTMASTER: Send address changes to The Yale Law Journal, P.O. Box 208215, New Haven, Connecticut 06520-8215.

    SUBSCRIPTIONS. A year subscription for Volume 121 is $55.00 payable in advance (please see our website for overseas shipping charges). Remittance must be made by U.S. Dollar drafts payable at a U.S. bank. Unfortunately, we are not able to accept payments in cash or by credit card. Subscription requests received after the first issue of a volume has been printed will run for eight consecutive issues unless otherwise indicated by the subscriber. Subscription backstarting is not permitted to include prior volume years. Overseas delivery is not guaranteed.

    CLAIMS. Domestic claims for non-receipt of issues should be made within 90 days of the month of publication, overseas claims within 180 days; thereafter, the regular back issue rate will be charged for replacement. All subscriptions will be renewed automatically unless the subscriber provides timely notice of cancellation prior to the start of a new volume year. Address changes must be made at least two months before publication date. Please provide an old mailing label or the entire old address; the new address must include the ZIP code. Address changes or other requests for subscription information should be directed to the Business Manager.

    SINGLE AND BACK ISSUES. Each issue of Volume 121 of the Journal can be purchased prepaid from The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. for $25 (check must accompany order). For Connecticut deliveries, add 6% state sales tax. Remittance must be made by U.S. Dollar drafts payable to a U.S. bank. Unfortunately, we are not able to accept payments in cash or credit card. To purchase back issues from Volumes 1-120, please contact William S. Hein and Company, Inc., 1285 Main Street, Buffalo, New York 14209, (800) 828-7571. Back issues can also be found in electronic format on HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org/).

    MANUSCRIPTS. The Journal invites the submission of unsolicited articles, essays, and book reviews. Manuscripts must be submitted online at http://yalelawjournal.org/submissions.html.

    COPYRIGHT. Copyright © 2012 by The Yale Law Journal Company, Inc. Requests for copyright permissions should be directed to Copyright Clearance Center, 222 Rosewood Drive, Danvers, MA 01923, (978) 750-8400, http://www.copyright.com/.

    PRODUCTION. Citations in the Journal conform to The Bluebook: A Uniform System of Citation (19th ed. 2010), copyright by The Columbia Law Review Association, The Harvard Law Review Association, the University of Pennsylvania Law Review, and The Yale Law Journal. The Journal is printed by Joe Christensen, Inc., in Lincoln, Nebraska. Periodicals postage paid at New Haven, Connecticut, and additional mailing offices. Publication number ISSN 0044-0094.

    INTERNET ADDRESS. The Yale Law Journal’s homepage is located at http://www.yalelawjournal.org.

    YALE LAW SCHOOL

    OFFICERS OF ADMINISTRATION

       Richard Charles Levin, B.A., B.Litt., Ph.D., President of the University

       Peter Salovey, A.B., M.A., Ph.D., Provost of the University

       Robert C. Post, A.B., J.D., Ph.D., Dean

       Douglas Kysar, B.A., J.D., Deputy Dean

       S. Blair Kauffman, B.S., B.A., J.D., LL.M., M.L.L., Law Librarian

       Megan A. Barnett, B.A., J.D., Associate Dean

       Sharon C. Brooks, B.A., J.D., Assistant Dean

       Toni Hahn Davis, B.A., J.D., M.S.W., LL.M., Associate Dean

       Brent Dickman, B.B.A., M.B.A., Associate Dean

       Mark LaFontaine, B.A., J.D., Associate Dean

       Asha Rangappa, A.B., J.D., Associate Dean

       Mike K. Thompson, B.A., M.B.A., J.D., Associate Dean

    FACULTY EMERITI

       Guido Calabresi, B.S., B.A., LL.B., M.A., Dr.Jur., LL.D., D.Phil., H.Litt.D., D.Poli.Sci., Sterling Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Dennis E. Curtis, B.S., LL.B., Clinical Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Harlon Leigh Dalton, B.A., J.D., Professor Emeritus of Law

       Carroll L. Lucht, B.A., M.S.W., J.D., Clinical Professor Emeritus of Law, Supervising Attorney, and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Mirjan Radovan Damaška, LL.B., Dr.Jur., Sterling Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Jan Ginter Deutsch, LL.B., Ph.D., Walter Hale Hamilton Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Owen M. Fiss, B.A., B.Phil., LL.B., Sterling Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Michael J. Graetz, B.B.A., LL.B., LL.D., Justus S. Hotchkiss Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Quintin Johnstone, B.A., J.S.D., Justus S. Hotchkiss Professor Emeritus of Law

       Carol M. Rose, B.A., M.A., J.D., Ph.D., Gordon Bradford Tweedy Professor Emeritus of Law and Organization, and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Peter H. Schuck, B.A., M.A., J.D., LL.M., Simeon E. Baldwin Professor Emeritus and Professor (Adjunct) of Law

       John G. Simon, B.A., LL.B., LL.D., Augustus E. Lines Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Stephen Wizner, A.B., J.D., William O. Douglas Clinical Professor Emeritus of Law, Supervising Attorney, and Professorial Lecturer in Law

    FACULTY

    † Bruce Ackerman, B.A., LL.B., Sterling Professor of Law and Political Science

       Muneer I. Ahmad, A.B., J.D., Clinical Professor of Law

       Anne L. Alstott, A.B., J.D., Professor of Law

    ‡ Akhil Reed Amar, B.A., J.D., Sterling Professor of Law

       Ian Ayres, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., William K. Townsend Professor of Law

       Jack M. Balkin, A.B., J.D., Ph.D., Knight Professor of Constitutional Law and the First Amendment

       Aharon Barak, LL.M., Dr.Jur., Visiting Professor of Law and Gruber Global Constitutionalism Fellow (fall term)

       Barton Beebe, B.A., Ph.D., J.D., Anne Urowsky Visiting Professor of Law (fall term)

       Raymond Brescia, B.A., J.D., Visiting Clinical Associate Professor of Law

       Lea Brilmayer, B.A., J.D., LL.M., Howard M. Holtzmann Professor of International Law

    † Richard R.W. Brooks, B.A., M.A., Ph.D., J.D., Leighton Homer Surbeck Professor of Law

    ‡ Robert A. Burt, B.A., M.A., J.D., Alexander M. Bickel Professor of Law

       Guido Calabresi, B.S., B.A., LL.B., M.A., Dr.Jur., LL.D., D.Phil., H.Litt.D., D.Poli.Sci., Sterling Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

    ‡ Stephen Lisle Carter, B.A., J.D., William Nelson Cromwell Professor of Law

    ‡ Amy Chua, A.B., J.D., John M. Duff, Jr. Professor of Law

       Jules L. Coleman, B.A., M.S.L., Ph.D., Wesley Newcomb Hohfeld Professor of Jurisprudence and Professor of Philosophy

       Dennis E. Curtis, B.S., LL.B., Clinical Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Hanoch Dagan, LL.B., LL.M., J.S.D., Visiting Professor of Law and Oscar M. Ruebhausen Distinguished Senior Fellow (fall term)

       Harlon Leigh Dalton, B.A., J.D., Professor Emeritus of Law

       Mirjan Radovan Damaška, LL.B., Dr.Jur., Sterling Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Drew S. Days, III, B.A., LL.B., Alfred M. Rankin Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Jan Ginter Deutsch, B.A., LL.B., Ph.D., M.A., Walter Hale Hamilton Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Fiona Doherty, B.A., J.D., Visiting Clinical Associate Professor of Law

    ‡ Steven Barry Duke, B.S., J.D., LL.M., Professor of Law

    † Robert C. Ellickson, A.B., LL.B., Walter E. Meyer Professor of Property and Urban Law

       Edwin Donald Elliott, B.A., J.D., Professor (Adjunct) of Law

    ‡ William N. Eskridge, Jr., B.A., M.A., J.D., John A. Garver Professor of Jurisprudence

    * Daniel C. Esty, A.B., M.A., J.D., Hillhouse Professor of Environmental Law and Policy, School of Forestry & Environmental Studies; and Clinical Professor of Environmental Law and Policy, Law School

       Stanley Fish, B.A., M.A., Ph.D., Visiting Professor of Law and Oscar M. Ruebhausen Distinguished Senior Fellow (fall term)

       Owen M. Fiss, B.A., B.Phil., LL.B., Sterling Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

    ‡ James Forman Jr., A.B., J.D., Clinical Professor of Law

       Bryan Garsten, B.A., M.Phil., Ph.D., Professor (Adjunct) of Law (spring term)

       Heather K. Gerken, B.A., J.D., J. Skelly Wright Professor of Law

    ‡ Paul Gewirtz, B.A., J.D., Potter Stewart Professor of Constitutional Law

       Robert W. Gordon, A.B., J.D., Chancellor Kent Professor of Law and Legal History

       Michael J. Graetz, B.B.A., LL.B., LL.D., Justus S. Hotchkiss Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Dieter Grimm, LL.M., Dr.Jur., Visiting Professor of Law and Gruber Global Constitutionalism Fellow (spring term)

       Lani Guinier, B.A., J.D., Visiting Professor of Law (fall term)

    ‡ Henry B. Hansmann, A.B., J.D., Ph.D., Augustus E. Lines Professor of Law

       Robert D. Harrison, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Lecturer in Legal Method

       Oona Hathaway, B.A., J.D., Gerard C. and Bernice Latrobe Smith Professor of International Law

       Kristin Henning, B.A., J.D., LL.M., Sidley Austin-Robert D. McLean ’70 Visiting Clinical Professor of Law (spring term)

       Daniel E. Ho, B.A., A.M., Ph.D., J.D., Maurice R. Greenberg Visiting Professor of Law (spring term)

       Quintin Johnstone, B.A., J.S.D., Justus S. Hotchkiss Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Christine Jolls, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Gordon Bradford Tweedy Professor of Law and Organization

    * Dan M. Kahan, B.A., J.D., Elizabeth K. Dollard Professor of Law

       Paul W. Kahn, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Robert W. Winner Professor of Law and the Humanities, and Director, Orville H. Schell, Jr. Center for International Human Rights

       Pamela S. Karlan, B.A., J.D., Visiting Professor of Law (fall term)

       S. Blair Kauffman, B.S., B.A., J.D., LL.M., M.L.L., Law Librarian and Professor of Law

       Daniel Kevles, B.A., Ph.D., Professor (Adjunct) of Law (spring term)

       Alvin K. Klevorick, B.A., M.A., Ph.D., John Thomas Smith Professor of Law and Professor of Economics

    * Harold Hongju Koh, A.B., B.A., J.D., M.A., Martin R. Flug ’55 Professor of International Law

    * Anthony Townsend Kronman, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Sterling Professor of Law

       Douglas Kysar, B.A., J.D., Deputy Dean and Joseph M. Field ’55 Professor of Law

       John H. Langbein, A.B., LL.B., Ph.D., Sterling Professor of Law and Legal History

       Sanford Levinson, B.A., Ph.D., J.D., Visiting Professor of Law (fall term)

    * Yair Listokin, A.B., M.A., Ph.D., J.D., Associate Professor of Law

       Carroll L. Lucht, B.A., M.S.W., J.D., Clinical Professor Emeritus of Law, Supervising Attorney, and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Jonathan R. Macey, A.B., J.D., Sam Harris Professor of Corporate Law, Corporate Finance, and Securities Law

       Miguel Maduro, Dr.Jur., Visiting Professor of Law and Gruber Global Constitutionalism Fellow (fall term)

    † Daniel Markovits, B.A., M.Sc., D.Phil., J.D., Professor of Law

    ‡ Jerry Louis Mashaw, B.A., LL.B., Ph.D., Sterling Professor of Law

       Tracey L. Meares, B.S., J.D., Walton Hale Hamilton Professor of Law

       Noah Messing, B.A., J.D., Lecturer in the Practice of Law and Legal Writing

       Jeffrey A. Meyer, B.A., J.D., Visiting Professor of Law

       Samuel Moyn, B.A., M.A., Ph.D., J.D., Irving S. Ribicoff Visiting Professor of Law (spring term)

       Nicholas Parrillo, A.B., M.A., J.D., Associate Professor of Law

    † Jean Koh Peters, A.B., J.D., Sol Goldman Clinical Professor of Law and Supervising Attorney

       Robert C. Post, A.B., J.D., Ph.D., Dean and Sol & Lillian Goldman Professor of Law

       J.L. Pottenger, Jr., A.B., J.D., Nathan Baker Clinical Professor of Law and Supervising Attorney

    † Claire Priest, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Professor of Law

    ‡ George L. Priest, B.A., J.D., Edward J. Phelps Professor of Law and Economics and Kauffman Distinguished Research Scholar in Law, Economics, and Entrepreneurship

       William Michael Reisman, B.A., J.S.D., Myres S. McDougal Professor of International Law

       Judith Resnik, B.A., J.D., Arthur Liman Professor of Law

       Roberta Romano, B.A., M.A., J.D., Sterling Professor of Law and Director, Yale Law School Center for the Study of Corporate Law

       Carol M. Rose, B.A., M.A., J.D., Ph.D., Gordon Bradford Tweedy Professor Emeritus of Law and Organization, and Professorial Lecturer in Law

    † Susan Rose-Ackerman, B.A., Ph.D., Henry R. Luce Professor of Jurisprudence (Law School and Department of Political Science)

       Jed Rubenfeld, A.B., J.D., Robert R. Slaughter Professor of Law

       Peter H. Schuck, B.A., M.A., J.D., LL.M., Simeon E. Baldwin Professor Emeritus of Law and Professor (Adjunct) of Law

       Vicki Schultz, B.A., J.D., Ford Foundation Professor of Law

    † Alan Schwartz, B.S., LL.B., Sterling Professor of Law

       Ian Shapiro, B.Sc., M.Phil., Ph.D., J.D., Professor (Adjunct) of Law (spring term)

       Scott J. Shapiro, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Professor of Law and Philosophy

       Robert J. Shiller, B.A., Ph.D., Professor (Adjunct) of Law (fall term)

    † Reva Siegel, B.A., M.Phil., J.D., Nicholas deB. Katzenbach Professor of Law

       James J. Silk, A.B., M.A., J.D., Clinical Professor of Law, Allard K. Lowenstein International Human Rights Clinic, and Executive Director, Orville H. Schell, Jr. Center for International Human Rights

       John G. Simon, B.A., LL.B., LL.D., Augustus E. Lines Professor Emeritus of Law and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Robert A. Solomon, B.A., J.D., Clinical Professor of Emeritus of Law

       Kate Stith, A.B., M.P.P., J.D., Lafayette S. Foster Professor of Law

       Alec Stone Sweet, B.A., M.A., Ph.D., Leitner Professor of International Law, Politics, and International Studies

       Gerald Torres, A.B., J.D., LL.M., Maurice R. Greenberg Visiting Professor of Law (fall term)

       James Q. Whitman, J.D., Ph.D., Ford Foundation Professor of Comparative and Foreign Law

       Ralph Karl Winter, Jr., B.A., LL.B., Professor (Adjunct) of Law

       Michael J. Wishnie, B.A., J.D., Clinical Professor of Law and Director, Jerome N. Frank Legal Services Organization

    † John Fabian Witt, B.A., J.D., Ph.D., Allen H. Duffy Class of 1960 Professor of Law

       Stephen Wizner, A.B., J.D., William O. Douglas Clinical Professor Emeritus of Law, Supervising Attorney, and Professorial Lecturer in Law

       Howard V. Zonana, B.A., M.D., Professor of Psychiatry and Clinical Professor (Adjunct) of Law

    * On leave of absence, 2011—2012.

    † On leave of absence, fall term, 2011.

    ‡ On leave of absence, spring term, 2012.

    LECTURERS IN LAW

       John C. Balzano, B.A., M.A., J.D.

       Nicholas Bramble, B.A., M.A., J.D.

       Adam S. Cohen, A.B., J.D.

       Linda Greenhouse, B.A., M.S.L., Joseph Goldstein Lecturer in Law

       Lucas Guttentag, A.B., J.D.

       Jamie P. Horsley, M.A., J.D.

       Katherine Kennedy, A.B., J.D., Timothy B. Atkeson Environmental Lecturer in Law

       Theresa J. Lee, B.A., M.A., J.D.

       Jeffrey M. Prescott, B.A., J.D., (on leave)

       Jamin Raskin, B.A., J.D.

       Sia Sanneh, B.A., M.A., J.D.

       Daniel Wade, B.A., M.A., M.Div., M.S., J.D.

    VISITING LECTURERS IN LAW

       Josh Abramowitz, B.A., J.D.

       Guillermo Aguilar-Alvarez, Lic. en Derecho (J.D.)

       Stephen Bright, B.A., J.D., Harvey Karp Visiting Lecturer in Law

       G. Eric Brunstad, Jr., B.A., J.D., LL.M.

       Cynthia Carr, B.A., J.D., LL.M.

       Brett Cohen, B.A., J.D.

       Eugene R. Fidell, B.A., LL.B., Florence Rogatz Visiting Lecturer in Law

       Lawrence J. Fox, B.A., J.D., George W. and Sadella D. Crawford Visiting Lecturer in Law

       Eugene Garver, A.B., Ph.D.

       Nancy Gertner, B.A., M.A., J.D.

       Frank Iacobucci, LL.B., LL.M., Gruber Global Constitutionalism Fellow and Visiting Lecturer in Law

       Benjamin Heineman, B.A., B.Litt., J.D.

       Howard Kahn, A.B., Ph.D.

       Brett M. Kavanaugh, B.A., J.D.

       Mark R. Kravitz, B.A., J.D.

       Daryl J. Levinson, A.B., M.A., J.D.

       Barbara Marcus, B.A., M.S., Ph.D.

       Braxton McKee, M.D.

       Andrew J. Pincus, B.A., J.D.

       Charles A. Rothfeld, A.B., J.D.

       John M. Samuels, B.A., J.D., LL.M.

       David A. Schultz, B.A., M.A., J.D.

       Michael Solender, B.A., J.D.

       Ko-Yung Tung, B.A., J.D.

       Stefan Underhill, B.A., J.D.

       Neil Walker, LL.B., Ph.D.

       John M. Walker, Jr., B.A., J.D.

    THE YALE LAW JOURNAL

    VOLUME 121

    Rights and Votes

    DARYL J. LEVINSON

    [cite as 121 YALE L.J. 1286 (2012)]

    ABSTRACT. This Article explores the functional similarities, residual differences, and interrelationships between rights and votes, both conceived as tools for protecting minorities (or other vulnerable groups) from the tyranny of majorities (or other dominant social and political actors). The Article starts from the simple idea that the interests of vulnerable groups in collective decisionmaking processes can be protected either by disallowing certain outcomes that would threaten those interests (using rights) or by enhancing the power of these groups within the decisionmaking process to enable them to protect their own interests (using votes). Recognizing that rights and votes can be functional substitutes for one another in this way, the Article proceeds to ask why, or under what circumstances, political and constitutional actors might prefer one to the other — or some combination of both. While the primary focus is on constitutional law and design, the Article shows that similar choices between rights and votes arise in many different areas of law, politics, and economic organization, including international law and governance, corporations, criminal justice, and labor and employment law.

    AUTHOR. David Boies Professor of Law, New York University School of Law. Thanks to Gabriella Blum, Ryan Bubb, John Ferejohn, Barry Friedman, Heather Gerken, Ryan Goodman, Bernard Grofman, Don Herzog, Roderick Hills, Daniel Hulsebosch, Michael Klarman, Robert Keohane, Janos Kis, Douglas Laycock, Michael Levine, Dotan Oliar, Benjamin Sachs, Adam Samaha, Peter Schuck, Matthew Stephenson, and Adrian Vermeule, and to participants in workshops at Harvard Law School, New York University School of Law, and University of Virginia School of Law, for useful comments on drafts.

    ARTICLE CONTENTS

    INTRODUCTION

    I. RIGHTS OR REPRESENTATION

    A. Constitutional Structure and Rights

    B. Constitutional Protection for Slavery

    C. Emergencies and Executive Power

    D. Rights as Representation Reinforcement

    E. Voting Rights and Civil Rights

    F. Comparative Constitutional Design

    G. Democratization, Rights, and Redistribution

    H. Global Governance

    I. Corporate Law

    J. Labor and Employment Law

    K. Juries, Race, and Representation in Criminal Justice

    II. HOW TO CHOOSE?

    A. Absoluteness Versus Flexibility

    B. Durability

    C. Democratic Limitations

    D. Expression and Acculturation

    E. Summary

    III. BEYOND RIGHTS VERSUS VOTES

    A. Rights and Votes as Complements

    B. A Third Option: Exit and Autonomy

    CONCLUSION

    INTRODUCTION

    Rights and votes are commonly cast in stark opposition to one another. Theorists of political liberalism and justice tend to view rights as extrapolitical limitations on democratic decisionmaking. Constitutional lawyers, too, have long been obsessed with what they see as an inherent conflict between constitutional rights and democracy—and, at the institutional level, between judicial and legislative supremacy. Even where rights and votes are not pitted against each other, they are treated as categorically different phenomena. Disciplinary boundaries divide political and constitutional theorists — who tend to think in terms of rights and equality — from political scientists and election law scholars who are interested in the organization of power.¹ The division between rights and votes also cuts through the middle of constitutional law. A central organizing principle of doctrine, scholarship, and curriculum is the distinction between the structural provisions of the Constitution, which create the institutional framework of democratic government, and the rights provisions, which place limits on what that government is permitted to do.

    Yet rights and votes need not be seen as working at cross-purposes or taxonomized as deeply different kinds. At least in some settings, rights and votes might be viewed instead as compatible tools for performing the same basic job. In particular, both can be used in domains of collective decisionmaking to protect minorities (or other vulnerable groups) from the tyranny of majorities (or other dominant social and political actors).² One way of protecting a minority is to create and enforce rights against majoritarian exploitation. Another is to structure the political process so that minorities are empowered to protect themselves.

    In fact, rights and votes have been viewed as functionally similar in this way in a wide array of constitutional and political contexts. For example, the Framers of the U.S. Constitution attempted to protect the rights of property owners, religious dissenters, and other minorities by creating a structure of government that would politically empower these groups to block any attempt by overbearing majorities to trample their interests. James Madison and the other Federalist Framers dismissed the enumeration of rights — as in the Bill of Rights — as a less effective means to the same ends. More recent constitutional designers concerned with protecting ethnic and religious minorities have confronted the same choice between relying on mechanisms of political empowerment and rights backed by judicial review. The NAACP in the Jim Crow South had to decide whether to allocate resources to securing access to the ballot or to strengthening substantive rights protection — whether to push first for the Voting Rights Act or for the Civil Rights Act.³ Courts and constitutional theorists, too, have recognized that rights can compensate for the absence of political empowerment: this is the pivotal insight of process theorists like John Hart Ely and arguably the basis for much of the Supreme Court’s post-New Deal rights jurisprudence on the Carolene Products Footnote Four model.⁴ Courts have leveraged the functional similarities of rights and votes in other ways, as well. During times of war and crisis, for instance, the Supreme Court has attempted to protect civil rights and liberties indirectly by bolstering political checks on executive power.⁵

    Consolidating and abstracting from these and other examples, this Article explores the functional similarities, residual differences, and interactions between rights and votes as tools for minority protection. The Article starts from the simple idea that the interests of vulnerable groups in collective decisionmaking processes can be protected either by disallowing certain outcomes that would threaten those interests (using rights) or by enhancing the power of these groups within the decisionmaking process to enable them to protect their own interests (using votes). Recognizing that rights and votes can be functional substitutes for one another, the Article proceeds to ask why, or under what circumstances, political and constitutional actors might prefer one to the other — or some combination of both.

    More specifically, the Article is organized as follows. Part I surveys a range of contexts in which rights and votes have been recognized as alternative mechanisms for protecting the important interests of minorities and other vulnerable groups. While the primary focus is on constitutional law and design, the survey in Part I shows that similar choices between rights and votes arise in many different areas of law, politics, and economic organization, including international law and governance, corporations, criminal justice, and labor and employment law. In all of these contexts, rights and votes can serve as functional substitutes for one another.

    That said, rights and votes are not always perfect substitutes. Drawing on the examples surveyed in Part I, Part II identifies and critically examines the most commonly cited differences between rights and votes that have been thought to bear on the choice of whether to use one or the other. One such difference operates along the dimension of breadth versus depth. Votes offer minorities and other groups the ability to exert influence over a broad range of issues, but with no guarantee of prevailing. Rights potentially offer such a guarantee, but only for a restricted range of issues. Along a different dimension, voting arrangements are generally believed to be more durable — more resilient against majoritarian opposition — than rights. A number of additional considerations, on the other hand, seem to weigh in favor of rights. For example, votes may be of little value for individuals and small minorities; attempts to bolster the political power of minorities may vest these groups with undesirable holdout power and generate high decision costs; and limitations on the permissible or practical scope of the political community may render some groups ineligible for political enfranchisement in the first place. Part II discusses these and other considerations that may influence the choice between rights and votes in any given setting.

    Part III extends the central analysis of the Article in two directions. First, rights and votes are not just substitutes but also, in some circumstances, complements. Section III.A discusses a number of respects in which political representation may enhance the value of rights, and the other way around. Groups may need political power to preserve and enforce their rights, and rights may generate or be preconditions for the meaningful exercise of democratic political power. Second, rights and votes are not the only means of protecting minorities and other vulnerable groups from the outcomes of collective decisionmaking. Section III.B moves beyond rights and votes to consider a third common method of protecting minorities: federalism (or a range of institutional analogues). Rather than empowering minorities to exercise greater voice in political decisionmaking processes or using rights to protect them against particularly unfavorable outcomes from those processes, minority groups can be permitted to exit the larger political community and exercise autonomous decisionmaking authority in a community of their own. The discussion in this Section describes how decentralized governance arrangements offer a third alternative to rights and votes in some contexts and then proceeds to explore some of the relative advantages and disadvantages of that approach.

    To avoid confusion, it should be noted at the outset that the Article’s use of the terms rights and votes may depart somewhat from ordinary meanings. Here, votes are understood to include not just ballots but also any form of representation or direct participation in processes of collective decisionmaking, or any institutional or structural arrangement of those processes that better enables groups to influence outcomes. Giving a minority group votes, in this expansive sense of the term, can mean enfranchising them at the polls. But it can also mean bolstering their voice through redistricting or proportional representation; increasing their decisionmaking power within the legislature by requiring supermajority votes or creating vetogates; facilitating pluralist bargaining or nonelectoral channels of influence through which minorities can exercise meaningful political voice even if they are outvoted; or creating structures and institutions like the separation of powers or the United States Senate that similarly empower numerical minorities to block or influence policy.

    The analytic framework of the Article draws a further distinction between votes and exit in the form of decentralized, autonomous decisionmaking by particular groups or outright secession. Regrettably, this distinction cuts across the conventional category of constitutional structure, which is commonly understood to include both the electoral and institutional framework of national democracy (i.e., votes) and federalism (i.e., exit).⁶ Lumping federalism together with separation of powers has some advantages from the parochial perspective of U.S. constitutional law, but it elides the more broadly useful distinction, emphasized here, between empowering a group within a collective decisionmaking process (i.e., votes) and empowering the group to make its own decisions through a separate decisionmaking process (i.e., exit).⁷

    As for rights, the term is applied broadly throughout the Article to characterize a wide range of substantive limitations on the permissible outcomes of collective decisionmaking processes. Also included under the rubric of rights in some contexts are affirmative entitlements to certain substantive outcomes — positive, welfare, and second or third generation kinds of rights, in addition to the traditional liberal or negative varieties. On the other hand, what are conventionally called voting rights are categorized for present purposes not as rights but as votes.⁸ In the modern world of constitutional law and theory, rights are strongly associated with judicial interpretation, specification, and enforcement, and the Article correspondingly pays special attention to judicially enforced rights. But given that judicial enforcement is not a prerequisite for meaningful rights protection,⁹ rights should not be understood as limited or reducible to the judicially enforced variety. Moreover, as the Article emphasizes throughout, voting rules are also subject to judicial enforcement.¹⁰ This is a further reason for treating the role of the judiciary as a separate variable, apart from the choice of rights and votes.

    Abstracting from all of this definitional complexity, the distinction between rights and votes might be understood simply as a special case of the more general distinction between process and substance (or between means and ends). Indeed, at a very high level of generality, the Article’s contribution might be viewed merely as reiterating the familiar critical refrain that such distinctions do not run very deep. Like all procedural arrangements, votes predictably affect substantive outcomes. Consequently, outcome-based concerns can be addressed in either of two ways. The direct way is simply to specify up front that certain outcomes must (not) be produced. The indirect way is to allocate decisionmaking power or structure decisionmaking processes in such a way as to stack the deck in favor of desirable outcomes or against undesirable ones. If this observation is in some general sense familiar, it also remains surprisingly generative. Or so the discussion that follows will attempt to show.

    I. RIGHTS OR REPRESENTATION

    Rights and votes appear as functional alternatives in a broad range of settings in which collective decisionmaking processes threaten the interests of minorities and other vulnerable groups. The collection of examples that follows serves to illustrate the ubiquity of the choice between the two types of devices and the array of institutional forms each can take.

    A. Constitutional Structure and Rights

    A conventional divide in constitutional law separates structure from rights. The structural parts of the U.S. Constitution — consisting primarily of the first three Articles, which constitute the three branches of the federal government — are supposed to create a framework for democratic governance. Rights provisions, such as those enumerated in the Bill of Rights, are supposed to protect individuals and minorities against majoritarian abuses perpetrated through that framework.¹¹

    But the rights/structure distinction is in many ways misleading. For one thing, it obscures the fact that the Bill of Rights, as originally conceived, was as much about protecting the political decisionmaking power of local majorities as about protecting the rights of individuals and minorities. Many of the rights it enumerated were meant not to protect against majoritarian tyranny, but, quite the opposite, to bolster majoritarian governance by placing limits on the self-serving behavior of federal officials and by safeguarding institutions of state and local self-government to insulate citizens from these officials’ despotic reach.¹² More relevant for present purposes, separating structure from rights misses the point that the original design of the Constitution relied primarily on structural arrangements to protect rights.¹³ Convinced that direct protection of constitutionally enumerated rights would be futile, the Federalist Framers, led by James Madison, attempted to secure rights indirectly, by creating a structure of government that would empower vulnerable groups to protect their interests through the political process.

    To elaborate, the Framers were concerned about two different types of potentially vulnerable groups. The first was the citizenry at large — majorities — who might be tyrannized or plundered by despotic federal officials. This is a worst-case version of the inevitable agency problems of representative government. The Framers were also concerned that the principal-agent relationship between constituents and their representatives could become too tight, allowing dominant factions of the electorate to capture government for their own selfish ends—including, especially, the oppression of minorities.¹⁴ As Madison drew the distinction in Federalist No. 51, It is of great importance in a republic not only to guard the society against the oppression of its rulers, but to guard one part of the society against the injustice of the other part.¹⁵

    It was this latter problem, of faction, that Madison (among others) had come to believe was the most worrisome.¹⁶ In our Governments, Madison wrote,

    the real power lies in the majority of the Community, and the invasion of private rights is cheifly to be apprehended, not from acts of Government contrary to the sense of its constituents, but from acts in which the Government is the mere instrument of the major number of the constituents.¹⁷

    At the same time, however, Madison doubted that constitutional rights could do much to prevent political majorities or other powerful factions from having their way. The problem was that countermajoritarian rights could not be backed by the dread of an appeal to any other force within the community more powerful than the very majorities who posed the threat.¹⁸ On the assumption that the political and physical power in society were both lodged in a majority of the people,¹⁹ countermajoritarian rights would simply be disregarded or overridden when push came to shove.²⁰

    Madison and the other Framers decided to take a different tack. Rather than attempting to enumerate and protect rights directly, they contrived a structure of government that they hoped would protect individual liberty and minority interests indirectly. This structure had several important components. Perhaps most important of all, shifting power to the national government of the extended republic would bring more factions into competition with one another and therefore make it more difficult for a stable, unified majority to capture the government and tyrannize minorities.²¹ Madison made the case that the security for civil rights must be the same as that for religious rights. It consists in the one case in the multiplicity of interests, and in the other, in the multiplicity of sects.²² At the same time, Madison believed that large federal election districts and the indirect election of Senators and the President would select for representatives who would possess most wisdom to discern, and most virtue to pursue, the common good of the society and insulate them from the heat of majoritarian political pressure.²³ In this way, the constitutional structure of government would refine and enlarge the public views by passing them through the medium of a chosen body of citizens, whose wisdom may best discern the true interest of their country and whose patriotism and love of justice will be least likely to sacrifice it to temporary or partial considerations.²⁴

    One obvious drawback of the Framers’ structural solution to the problem of majority tyranny was that it threatened to exacerbate the problem of agency. A plan to empower democratically insulated federal officials was bound to stoke Anti-Federalists’ fears of a distant national government tyrannizing the local citizenry. Responding to this worry, Madison offered a further structural solution, this one focused on the branches of the federal government and on the relationship between the federal government and the states. Just as a multiplicity of factions would compete with and check one another in society and the electorate, Madison reasoned, competition among the branches and levels of government might create a self-enforcing check on potentially despotic national officials. Thus, Federalist No. 51 describes how the constitutional separation of powers between the legislative and executive branches invites [a]mbition... to counteract ambition.²⁵ Along similar lines, Madison suggested that state governments would be motivated and empowered through various channels of political influence to enforce the federal power-sharing arrangement built into the constitutional design and to protect their citizens against national tyranny.²⁶ Here again, the idea was that the structural design of government would create politically self-sustaining protections for the rights and liberties of citizens.

    In sum, Madison’s hope was that votes — here conceived very broadly as the constitutional structure of the national political process — would do the work of rights.²⁷ Viewed in this way, as Alexander Hamilton put it, [T]he [structural] Constitution is itself, in every rational sense, and to every useful purpose, A BILL OF RIGHTS.²⁸ Some decades after ratification, Madison continued to believe that [t]he only effectual safeguard to the rights of the minority, must be laid in such a basis and structure of the Government itself, as may afford, in a certain degree, directly or indirectly, a defensive authority in behalf of a minority having right on its side.²⁹

    B. Constitutional Protection for Slavery

    The constitutional law and politics of slavery, from the Founding through the Civil War, offers a vivid illustration of how constitutional structure was supposed to protect rights — in this case, the rights of slave owners. While it was generally accepted at the Founding that some sort of constitutional protection for slavery was a necessary condition for Southern states to join the Union, there was little inclination at the Philadelphia Convention to write explicit, substantive protections for slaveholders into the constitutional text.³⁰ In part, this was because some of the Framers were squeamish about that peculiar institution. Madison, for one, thought it would be wrong to admit in the Constitution the idea that there could be property in men.³¹ But it was also because Southern Federalists had internalized Madison’s more general approach to constitutional design. They were convinced that parchment guarantees for human bondage would not restrain a Northern majority committed to abolishing slavery.³² Thus, the Constitution contains no explicit, rights-like prohibition on national interference with slavery in the Southern states.³³

    The slaveholding South preferred to stake its fortunes on the structural design of the federal government. Proportional representation in the lower house of Congress and the Electoral College, bolstered by the Three-Fifths Clause, held out the hope of eventual Southern control of the House

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1