Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Beyond the Blurb: On Critics and Criticism
Beyond the Blurb: On Critics and Criticism
Beyond the Blurb: On Critics and Criticism
Ebook188 pages2 hours

Beyond the Blurb: On Critics and Criticism

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Beyond the Blurb is a selection of essays that identifies the most important principles of literary criticism and considers the relevance of those principles in the work of specific literary critics, including James Wood, Harold Bloom, and Susan Sontag. Intended for academic and general readers alike, this insightful collection of essay

LanguageEnglish
PublisherCow Eye Press
Release dateDec 1, 2016
ISBN9780990915058
Beyond the Blurb: On Critics and Criticism
Author

Daniel K. Green

Daniel Green is a literary critic whose essays and reviews have appeared in numerous publications both online and in print. He maintains the literary weblog, The Reading Experience, which he created in 2004.

Related to Beyond the Blurb

Related ebooks

Literary Criticism For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Beyond the Blurb

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Beyond the Blurb - Daniel K. Green

    INTRODUCTION

    ON CRITICS AND CRITICISM

    Ioffer this selection of essays as a kind of cross-section of the views I have expressed over the last ten years or so about the goals and practice of literary criticism, views published on my own literary blog, The Reading Experience, as well as in various literary and book review journals. Place of publication played a large role in determining both the content and the form these essays took, since the blog essentially gave me the freedom to write as I pleased. As it turned out, what pleased me was to critically examine not just works of literature past and present but also the critics and critical methods whose influence helps to determine how literature is perceived and how literary works are made meaningful for diverse and at times disparate readers. All of the essays that follow are animated by this impulse to explicate the assumptions behind a practice referred to by a common name—criticism—but carried out in numerous and often quite conflicting ways.

    The essays also of course reflect my own assumptions and preferences, and while certainly these are the assumptions and preferences that inform my work as a literary critic, in these considerations of critics and criticism I am making them explicit through commentary on other critics—although in the first section, titled Critical Issues, I do directly address the more general questions confronted by all critics, in the process making my own thinking about autonomy or the efficacy of close reading expressly clear. Combined with the essays in the following two sections, on the failures and successes of particular critics, these discussions of what I take to be among the most important concerns confronting the literary critic ultimately present a philosophy of criticism that consistently returns to a few core tenets.

    A literary work, whether in verse or prose, is worth taking seriously for its own sake, apart from any value it might have as the object of some other discourse or inquiry.

    Although it is true that notions of autonomy that attribute to works of literature some kind of metaphysical separation from other forms of human communication cannot literally be sustained, much can be gained by acknowledging that artistic autonomy is a worthy ideal that in essence simply seeks to make room for a conception of literature that identifies poems and novels as first of all the source of aesthetic contemplation, verbal works of art, rather than conventional communication or just another form of cultural discourse. Readers and critics are perfectly entitled to regard literary works in any way they want, of course, but to deliberately avoid initially engaging with them for their artistic value—the value with which their creators presumably most resolutely attempted to invest them—seems hardly in keeping with the animating purpose of literature as a form of expression. Perhaps readers need not seek out what Nabokov insisted on calling aesthetic bliss (although why not?), but that a work of literature might in fact produce such bliss would seem to be a fact about it that a literary critic, at any rate, should need to account for.

    The meaning of a literary work consists of the experience of reading it, not in abstracted themes that signify what the work is about.

    A literary work is an arrangement of language designed to be perceived as such, not to impart sense as do the words of speech or ordinary prose. Some construe this assertion to effectively be a denial of meaning in fiction or poetry, but in fact it opens up the possibility of multiple, even infinite, meanings as the reader responds to the formal and stylistic effects the work’s verbal processes make available, effects that can include the suggestion of meaning in its conventional sense—the writer is saying something—although exactly what is being said remains amorphous, indefinite. This meaning is fluid, provisional, enriching the reading experience, not replacing it with the inspection of texts for messages and ideas. If reading a work of literature is reduced to comprehending its theme, the experience itself has become at best a secondary goal, at worst, superfluous.

    The goal of the literary critic should be to describe the work at hand as carefully as possible by scrutinizing his/her own experience of reading it as conscientiously as possible. Judgment is contingent upon description.

    Even a 500-word book review, which is likely to accentuate evaluation, should convey the sense that the reviewer attended closely to the particular features of the work and has assessed its worth through honest reflection on the effects those features produce. Judgment without adequate description is useless as criticism, since it makes the critical act simply the expression of personal preference, the marshalling of suitable, if finally empty, terms of praise or censure.

    The experience of reading is the experience of language.

    In fiction and poetry we don’t read characters or setting or meter or even prose or verse. We read words shaped into sentences, figures, paragraphs, dialogue, stanzas, chapters, or, in the most synoptic application of language, made to suggest the presence of form, whether traditional narrative form or something more adventurous. My orientation to criticism was heavily influenced by New Criticism (something still being taught when I started graduate school), but what I took most from the New Critics was their close reading of the movements of language, so that I am inclined first of all to read fiction the way the New Critics read poetry, for the integrated effects of language, for the way the parts of the text make a whole and how the parts interrelate. Ultimately, of course, you can’t avoid discussing such things as characters and point of view, but those are themselves the textual artifacts of language.

    Criticism and scholarship are not the same thing.

    Some of the critics discussed in this book, Richard Poirier and Harold Bloom, for example, could be called scholars. They are also critics. Both Poirier and Bloom are primarily engaged in the analysis and/or appreciation of particular literary works (or writers), although certainly the quality of their analysis is greatly enhanced by the great scholarly knowledge of literature both of them possess. Most of what is now called academic criticism, however, is in fact scholarship, since its goal is not explication or evaluation but to create a body of knowledge about literature, or to locate works of literature in a specified context (a context that is itself usually of more interest to the critic than the work), whether that context is historical, political, cultural, or philosophical. I believe criticism should be reserved to describe the former activities, not the latter. This does not imply that criticism is more valuable than scholarship (or vice versa), more literary or more useful, merely that they are separate pursuits.

    The greatest challenge to the efficacy of criticism is posed by what is called experimental literature, although this challenge also allows criticism to demonstrate its importance in mediating among writers, readers, and literature as a whole.

    It is one thing for a critic to interpret the latest work of literary fiction or to help illuminate a work from the past that may have at one time been considered unconventional but now has become assimilated to critical norms, but when faced with a new work that does not conform to established norms, the critic’s task becomes much harder, as well as more crucial. The critic must balance insight into the ways this new and seemingly unfamiliar work might actually maintain a connection to traditional practice with acknowledging what is truly fresh about it. The first of these responsibilities is just as important as the second, since originality can make an impression only when its point of departure from convention can be clearly discerned. Beyond just noting an original strategy or expression, the critic must also try to account for its success or failure in the work itself. Thus to fairly consider a work of innovative poetry or fiction, a literary critic must have creditable knowledge of literary history but must as well have sympathy for and sensitivity to writers and works that seemingly disrupt or deviate from that history. Finally such a critic is charged with initiating a process of reconciling the new and disruptive with a literary history that the new work, if it is successful, is destined to join.

    These are, of course, my core beliefs about criticism, and certainly no one is obliged to share them or even to find them credible. They are the beliefs from which I wrote the essays in this book, and the beliefs that animate my own reviews of contemporary fiction. As should be clear enough, my views about criticism are closely tied to my views about literature. I value a kind of criticism that is capable of illuminating the sort of literary work I most admire, one that provokes, surprises, takes risks, but also satisfies aesthetically, in effect enlarging our perception of what can be considered aesthetic success.

    I could have chosen other or different pieces to include in this book (probably illustrating to the point of tedium how extensively I do return to the basic principles I’ve identified), but what I have included is meant to elucidate an approach to criticism that takes literature seriously by granting it a fundamental integrity as a form of art, doesn’t attempt to overshadow the literary work by subsuming it to another agenda or asserting the critic’s own superiority of intellect or sensibility, but does also assume that criticism acquires authority through being rigorously attentive and articulating persuasive standards of analysis. Criticism in this form is both dependent on and independent of literature itself. Criticism arises because some readers feel a need to talk about the reading experience, because works of literature do not explain themselves; they leave the motives and principles of their own composition implicit. At its best, criticism can make these motives and principles explicit, without trespassing against that zone of the unspoken upon which literature depends.

    Unless, of course, you are Jonathan Franzen, who believes that the work is a contract with its readers whose terms are thoroughly spelled out. Presumably this sort of work requires no critics. Mostly, though, such a notion just makes it clear why a writer like Franzen might not be worth reading in the first place.

    1

    CRITICAL ISSUES

    PART 1

    CRITICAL ISSUES

    While certain core principles inform almost everything I write about literature and literary criticism, the essays included here seem to distil the critical issues in a particularly direct and relevant way. Some of them could be called reviews, while others are simply responses to something I had read, responses that I managed to shape into essays in which I endeavored to both describe the source’s argument and make a coherent argument of my own. I’m not sure I would have ever attempted to write such essays as these were it not for the existence of The Reading Experience, of the literary blog in general.

    The essays explore, sometimes more, sometimes less explicitly, the concerns that unify my approach to criticism, especially the practice of close reading, the nature of literature as an aesthetic form, and the role of criticism itself. While I do not argue explicitly in these essays that reflection on such issues might be especially important in the critical discussion of current/contemporary literature, nevertheless this is a necessary and underlying assumption. To the extent that the kind of focus on the literary qualities of poetry and fiction, that is, on those qualities that make them first of all works of art, for which I advocate has been dismissed as old-fashioned or superficial, new books are in danger of receiving only the most cursory notice, the most uncritical celebration or takedown, otherwise left to fade into future obscurity.

    Close Reading

    In A Critic’s Manifesto (The New Yorker, Aug 28, 2012), Daniel Mendelsohn contends that to be a critic requires expertise, authority, and taste. He leaves out the most important attribute a critic should have: the ability to pay attention. In fact, without this one, the others Mendelsohn mentions are superfluous.

    Any defensible judgment about a work of literature must arise from observable features on which the judgment is based and to which the critic can return. This is where the distinction between having an opinion about a text and being able to support that opinion is real. An opinion is only a provisional conclusion until it can be allied with and clarified by specific illustration from the work, until the critic can point to those particulars of the work that prompted the opinion. An unsupported opinion may or may not contain implicit but unstated illustration of this kind, but as long as it’s unstated, it is not itself criticism. Not everyone wants to be a critic, of course, but a book review, for example, can’t really be taken seriously as criticism unless some text-based evidence is provided.

    Providing such evidence requires that the critic pay attention. Close attention. This would involve, at minimum, noting, in fiction, such conventional elements as narrative structure (especially variations in narrative structure), character development (especially the writer’s strategies for influencing our attitude toward characters), point of view, etc., but since fiction as a genre of literature is at its core the creation of illusions of such things as character, story, or setting through skillful manipulation of language, a critic needs ultimately to be able to focus on the writer’s invocation of language, on the text as an

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1