Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

The Second Birth: On the Political Beginnings of Human Existence
The Second Birth: On the Political Beginnings of Human Existence
The Second Birth: On the Political Beginnings of Human Existence
Ebook301 pages5 hours

The Second Birth: On the Political Beginnings of Human Existence

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Most scholars link the origin of politics to the formation of human societies, but in this innovative work, Tilo Schabert takes it even further back: to our very births. Drawing on mythical, philosophical, religious, and political thought from around the globe—including America, Europe, the Middle East, and China—The Second Birth proposes a transhistorical and transcultural theory of politics rooted in political cosmology. With impressive erudition, Schabert explores the physical fundamentals of political life, unveiling a profound new insight: our bodies actually teach us politics.
           
Schabert traces different figurations of power inherent to our singular existence, things such as numbers, time, thought, and desire, showing how they render our lives political ones—and, thus, how politics exists in us individually, long before it plays a role in the establishment of societies and institutions. Through these figurations of power, Schabert argues, we learn how to institute our own government within the political forces that already surround us—to create our own world within the one into which we have been born. In a stunning vision of human agency, this book ultimately sketches a political cosmos in which we are all builders, in which we can be at once political and free. 
LanguageEnglish
Release dateNov 20, 2015
ISBN9780226185156
The Second Birth: On the Political Beginnings of Human Existence

Related to The Second Birth

Related ebooks

History & Theory For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for The Second Birth

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    The Second Birth - Tilo Schabert

    The Second Birth

    The Second Birth

    On the Political Beginnings of Human Existence

    TILO SCHABERT

    TRANSLATED BY JAVIER IBÁÑEZ-NOÉ

    The University of Chicago Press

    Chicago and London

    Tilo Schabert is professor emeritus of political science at the University of Erlangen in Germany and has taught at several other institutions around the world. A former secretary general for the International Council for Philosophy and the Humanities at UNESCO, he is the author of many books in several different languages, including, in English, Boston Politics and How World Politics Is Made. Javier Ibáñez-Noé is associate professor of philosophy at Marquette University.

    The University of Chicago Press, Chicago 60637

    The University of Chicago Press, Ltd., London

    © 2015 by The University of Chicago

    All rights reserved. Published 2015.

    Printed in the United States of America

    Original publication: Tilo Schabert, Die zweite Geburt des Menschen. Von den politischen Anfängen menschlicher Existenz © 2009 Verlag Karl Alber, part of Verlag Herder GmbH, Freiburg im Breisgau

    24 23 22 21 20 19 18 17 16 15 1 2 3 4 5

    ISBN-13: 978-0-226-03805-6 (cloth)

    ISBN-13: 978-0-226-18515-6 (e-book)

    DOI: 10.7208/chicago/9780226185156.001.0001

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Schabert, Tilo, author.

    [Zweite Geburt des Menschen. English]

    The second birth : on the political beginnings of human existence / Tilo Schabert ; translated by Javier Ibáñez-Noé.

    pages ; cm

    Includes bibliographical references and index.

    ISBN 978-0-226-03805-6 (cloth : alk. paper) — ISBN 978-0-226-18515-6 (ebook) 1. Political science—Anthropological aspects. 2. Political science—Philosophy. 3. Political anthropology. 4. Civilization. I. Ibáñez-Noé, Javier, translator. II. Title.

    JA71.S276813 2015

    320.01—dc23

    2015010509

    ♾ This paper meets the requirements of ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992 (Permanence of Paper).

    My friend, why are the great gods in council?

    ENKIDU, after a dream, addressing Gilgamesh (Gilgamesh 6.11)

    Contents

    Preface

    Introduction

    At the Start

    In Number

    In Body

    In Action

    In Consciousness

    In Grace

    In the Divine

    In Thought

    In Creation

    In Eros

    In Time

    In Law

    In Freedom

    Epilogue

    Acknowledgments

    Notes

    Index

    Analytical Table of Contents

    Introduction

    Distinction between first and second birth

    The Gestalten of human life are Gestalten of power

    The reflection on the political

    To exist means to govern creatively

    At the Start

    Distinction between start and beginning

    What are beginnings?

    The first—bodily—birth

    Power is the Gestalt of humanity

    In Number

    Number is the mode of all creation

    From the One to the Many

    The world in an order of number

    Human beings in the order of number

    Number and language

    The beginning in number

    The One and the Many

    In Body

    The power of bodies

    The political problem of a bodily-spatial presence

    The primary question of power among human beings

    Body-politics: the image of the train station

    Bodies are prevented by bodies from reaching an understanding

    Bodies necessitate politics: comparison of human beings and angels

    The civilization humans need: a creation made of power

    The science of the founding of politics: Ibn Khaldûn on the establishment of a civilization that fashions human beings into human beings

    Human beings and their bodies: lonely and yet eloquent

    The message of bodies

    The doctrine of human bodies for the welfare of human beings

    The beginning from which human beings become sociable to each other

    The anthropophanous event

    Unsociability and sociability are never interchangeable conditions

    Toward a political world of human beings: a politics for bodies

    A world different from the world of bodies: visions of paradise

    The specific mode of bodily existence under paradisiacal conditions

    Ibn Khaldûn’s distinction between a hypothetically and an empirically proceeding political science

    Beyond historical time: paradisiacal times

    Images of human society under paradisiacal conditions: Hesiod, Empedocles, Plato, Huainanzi, Rousseau, Fichte, Sartre

    The para-empirical product of natural man

    Anthropogonic logic: its formulation in Chinese thought

    The modes of creation: political processes

    Through their beginnings human beings are actors in the politics of creation

    In Action

    Human beings exist in action and in no other way

    Pascal and Plato on human existence in constant movement

    The existence of human beings: an existence oriented toward power

    The great question: to act toward what and for what?

    Human beings as the beginning and the begetters of their actions

    Human beings come to the power of their action out of the beginning

    Lines of meaning in relation to the totality of existence

    The freedom of human beings to exist creatively

    In Consciousness

    For human beings the soul is the faculty of their existence

    In the clarity of consciousness

    The eyes of cognition are in principle not opened

    In the night of cognition

    The power to create as a power to destroy

    A Gestalt of power for the recognition of meaning

    The work of the soul

    In the soul what consciousness is becomes apparent

    Human beings as capable of humanity

    The polis human being

    The soul’s work of government

    The beginning of political society in the Gestalt of the power of consciousness

    The culmination of human life occurs politically

    In Grace

    The figuration of creation in the process of creation

    Humans on the path to their beginning

    The human way and a more beautiful way: grace

    Knowing in the Gestalt of grace

    The commandment of grace: you shall know, but you shall not be like God

    The modern revolt against the commandment

    The promise that human beings will become gods: the final motif in European (Western) thought

    The beginning that human beings earn through grace for their second birth

    Augustine’s anthropogonic-political interpretation of the biblical creation story

    Two political societies from the very beginning (in primo homine)

    The anthropogonic freedom that is revealed to human beings in grace

    The estrangement of the first human beings from God out of arrogance (superbia) and greed (avaritia)

    Unselfish love (caritas) and self-love (amor sui)

    In the Divine

    Divinity and thought: the Gestalten for any initiation of human civilization

    The care for freedom

    The architecture of human existence in the architecture of the world

    How do human beings learn to be human beings?

    Plato’s myth of the rule of Kronos, the god of care

    The message of the myth: human beings are now alone, and this is their great predicament

    Human beings must lead themselves and themselves take care of themselves

    There is a word for the care of human beings for themselves: politics

    Politics is mimesis of God

    The fundamental and the pragmatic meanings of political thought

    The question regarding political theory

    The care of human beings for their existence

    A political theory is present in every human society

    Political theory in the modern age

    A theory of politics is always a theory of a crisis of politics

    The classical nature of political theory

    Political theory and political practice

    In Thought

    The sociability of thought

    Thought: start and beginning

    The path toward the human community begins in thought

    Plato’s poleogony: (a) The founding of human civilization in the gradual process of its political formation

    Plato’s poleogeny: (b) A history both of falling apart and of creation

    The paradigm (paradeigma) of human society

    The power of actualization of the paradigm

    A creative power to give form or a creative power to annihilate

    In Creation

    Creation is separation 72–

    Creation falls apart as it emerges

    Reports: Dao De Jing, Huainanzi, Upanishads, Hesiod’s Theogony, ancient Egyptian hymns, the Koran, the Bible

    The falling apart of the One brought about by the One itself

    The world is a society of the unsociable

    A history lies in things

    In Eros

    Eros, the twofold beginning: both of the falling apart and of the unity of creation

    Order is the structure of chaos

    The dialogue on Eros in Plato’s Symposium

    Eros according to Empedocles: sociable love and divisive strife

    Who is Eros?

    Plato’s images of Eros: (a) The androgynous kind (genos androgynos): human beings, once a whole, were cut up and their nature is now desiring

    Plato’s images of Eros: (b) Souls of wax: in caring for their souls, human beings prepare their thought. They are the shapers, the form givers of their thought. Human beings become human beings in the structure of Eros

    Plato’s images of Eros: (c) Humans as marionettes: Eros, the choreograph, shapes human beings according to the way in which they have become disposed toward Eros

    The common and the heavenly Eros

    Everything finds itself in a Gestalt among Gestalten

    Caring for and healing Eros

    The night of evil

    The monstrous human being

    The eros tyrannos

    The caring, conciliatory, just Eros

    The way we should live

    The culture of the soul

    The eros philosophos

    The feast of thought

    In Time

    Human beings are occurrences of time

    What are human beings in time?

    Time is a deactualizing power

    Human beings can change time in time

    Time Gestalten

    The time of Creation and the time of annihilation

    In the Gestalt of time all civilization is a civilization of recurrence

    Plato on the question: Since when have human states existed?

    The extinction of states: the beginning is the creation of the end

    Plato on the beginnings of states in the Laws

    The highest form of civilization manifests itself in the time-Gestalt of the beginning

    The beginning of legislation

    Humans create, within time, their times

    Progress toward the good as well as toward the bad

    The temporal course of political civilization

    In Law

    Human beings alone can never guarantee the soundness of a society composed of human beings

    The poachers of the good of the community

    Human existence is shaped from the beginning for the law

    The second, political predicament

    The rule of law (an empire of laws, and not of men)

    Is the law the Absolute?

    Not one answer, but different answers

    Empirical exposition (Anonymous Iamblichi, Chrysippos, Heraclitus, Aristotle, Cicero, Hobbes)

    The validity of human laws

    Foreknowledge of the law in human beings

    The power of the law is the power that frees human beings for their humanity

    In Freedom

    The special status of the Gestalt of freedom

    Freedom as a guideline for making a choice

    Questions to ask on the basis of the preceding investigation

    Freedom and the power that comes into being from the soul

    The work of the soul: a political project

    The animae anarchia

    The framing of the first constitution of human beings: the emergence of the community of the forces of the soul

    The politics of the soul

    The essential elements of political reality (constitution, power, government) are prefigured in the politics of the soul

    The freely chosen constitutions of the soul of different human beings

    The reality of freedom is power

    Power is the paradigm of human politics

    Every human being defines his or her constitution

    Freedom opens up every form of politics. It is both a good power and a bad one

    The construction of a society of human beings in and according to the Gestalt of freedom

    The paradox of freedom

    Human beings’ natural right to freedom

    Every human being is the sovereign of his or her existence

    The transformation of bodily relations between human beings into juridical ones

    A constitution for freedom

    From the paradox of freedom to the paradox of power

    What is the paradox of power?

    How the paradox of power is put on stage

    The regency of freedom

    The second birth: human beings’ own free work

    Preface

    This book inquires anew into the question: Whence originates the political Gestalt of human life and what does it entail? In pursuit of this question the book attempts to undertake a transcultural and transhistorical grounding of political theory. The material for it has accordingly been taken from classical works of different cultural spheres. Ancient Greek, Jewish and Christian, Chinese, Arabic, ancient Egyptian, and Indian texts have been examined with regard to their fundamental claims. Analysis of these texts showed that the visions of the political existence of human beings that they entertain can be surprisingly similar. The parallels between pre-Socratic thought and Taoism, for instance, are striking. To take another example, Philo of Alexandria’s hermeneutical method is in no way inferior to modern hermeneutics. In this way, a body of knowledge that had largely fallen into oblivion owing to the advent of modernity could be recovered and made available for contemporary political theory. It is precisely this knowledge that has the potential for providing the foundation for transcultural commonalities in our own times.

    The methodology of the book is both transdisciplinary and empirical. I have had recourse not only to philosophical and political writings, but also to mythical, religious, and literary ones. The material itself has been allowed to set the course of the investigation; nothing has been introduced that is not present in that material or that cannot be illustrated through it.

    In order to compare and present traditions of thought from different civilizations, generous quotations from original documents—in translation—were unavoidable. In order to do justice to these texts, the scholarly diction utilized in their presentation and analysis had to be adapted both to their individual peculiarities and to the need to mediate among them. This was the only way to make accessible premodern, other rhythms of thinking and the mythical imagination, as well as the evocative style of traditions of thought that often believed themselves to be in direct contact with reality.

    Human dignity is closely connected with the dignity possessed by politics in human life. When politics is despised or abused, human beings despise or abuse themselves. But if they understand politics as their most important activity, and if they act accordingly, human beings make themselves in fact worthy of themselves. The present book proposes to validate this claim.

    Introduction

    We must begin with a distinction: the distinction between the first and the second birth. The first birth yields a finished human being, but finished only in his or her bodily constitution, and in no way in his or her human constitution. This is because human beings, through their bodies, and merely by the fact that they exist, are put in an inescapable predicament that encompasses the totality of their being. This predicament is associated with the need for food, clothing, space, assistance, protection, instruction, welfare, and, in consequence, the need for association with others. In a certain, apparently contradictory, manner, their bodily existence, for which they were born into life, takes away their very capacity to live. Human beings must first regain this capacity in, with, and through their bodies, i.e., through the event of their second birth.¹

    This second birth is, as will be shown, a political birth, because it is carried out (by virtue of the primordial predicament that explains everything concerning human beings) in an act of political caring for human beings by human beings. They take themselves caringly into their own hands, and make themselves the beginning of the work that is required of them, for the sake of securing their life and survival. This work is the work of government. The reason is this: before human beings lay the foundation for a political community, certain Gestalten are pregiven to them for the conduct of their life that make them entirely political from the very start of their life. What is meant here by Gestalt? This term may be generally defined as follows. If one wants to be creative, whatever is intended in the creative process must be attained within certain boundaries: an intended configuration within certain forms that have been observed, a wished-for consummation within certain solutions that have been found, and a desired connection within certain structures that have been discovered. Or—to give a different example—human beings, by reason of their bodies, take up a certain amount of space, each one for himself or herself, and have thereby a position of power. This is the reason why the act of maneuvering through a crowd in a train station is itself already a form of acting politically between the poles of discreet diplomacy and a war of bodies.

    The Gestalten pregiven to human beings for the conduct of their life are Gestalten of power. No one can evade them, unless he were to escape from life itself. The Gestalten of power, which inhere in their existence by reason of their existence, take hold of human beings from the very beginning, with their entrance into the world. This is the logic of creation.²

    These connections explain the view of the origins and primary forms of the political offered here. While the tradition of political thought, from its beginning, has equated the start of human politics with the founding of human communities, the possibility is explored here that the disposition for politics may be found already in the disposition of human creation (i.e., in bodies) and, in general, in the form of this world as a creation. Let it be clearly understood that there is nothing arbitrary about this enterprise. Rather, the materials for the present reflection on the political are taken, without exception, from the vast repository of mythical, philosophical, religious, and political reflection that informs us of the intellectual traditions of different civilizations. This reflection on the political is empirically found in these traditions, and the only surprising fact is that there is not already a book that presents it. An attempt to provide such a presentation is offered here. The political in human life must be exhibited in the in-between in which it is empirically located, i.e., between the start of human existence (which while giving rise to this existence is not identical to it) and the beginning that is then made by human beings themselves through the founding of political communities. The interpretation of this beginning offered by Aristotle has had too normative an effect. It prevented a visualization of the political cosmology and the political anthropogony that must be grasped prior to the zōon politikon.³

    The book is accordingly organized as a successive consideration of what we call here "Gestalten of power in the development of human life as well as in the establishment and preservation of a civilization for this life. This organizational sequence is indicated in the thematic table of contents and clarified step by step in the analytical table of contents. A second thematic sequence may be drawn by focusing on key points. The discussion here starts—as demanded by the book’s empirical methodology—with the fact of the body, and it determines the political in its primary physico-cosmological emergence; in the next logical step, it proceeds to grasp the political in those modes in which the subsequent creative efforts of human beings establish it, so that its power may be a civilizing power and may thus break and replace the power of bodies. (The actual history of Western civilization, which is based on the principle of freedom, starts, for example, with freedom rights vis-à-vis bodily force, namely, in the legal agreements concerning habeas corpus). A third and final organizational stage consists in the constant reiteration of the central claim of this book: Human beings are placed by their very birth (i.e., their first birth) in the mode of the political, and in this mode they are subjects of a government. They are such subjects throughout their whole existence, and that is exactly the problem: Why is human existence a matter of governing? Why are the concepts human being and government, considered existentially, identical? If and when human beings become conscious of this question—or, as happens more often, are made conscious of it—their existence opens itself to their true beginning. They then see the work of governing that lies before them. If they take it up and assume it, nothing changes, obviously, in their primarily political mode of existence, in which they are subjects of a government. And yet they become empowered in a unique way: They may now begin their existence—in the political mode of this existence—in a totally different manner. They themselves can consciously and purposefully appoint the government in their lives. Through this beginning, human beings create for themselves a freedom to be themselves. Through the political," they become creators of a political creation. They insert the work of the political world, which they have created, into a world that they have not created. On the one hand, everything stays for them the way it was, i.e., everything remains dominated by that first and unceasing question of human existence as such: Who governs? But, on the other hand, nothing stays quite the same, because now, in their capacity as authors of a work of government for the sake of their own existence, human beings are the agents who, in their creative freedom, work on the form that the political takes in their existence.

    This book proposes to show that human beings own their existence only when they are creative for it. If they are not, they lose their existence, and they perish with their bodies, which did not receive the care that they required. In carrying out their existence—and they do not have the option not to carry it out, because nothing in their existence stands still—human beings are always, in one way or another, making themselves human beings, i.e., capable of government. Human beings exercise, of course, government over themselves. Such a government takes place against the background of a vast and confused multiplicity of forces that exist in them and that pull them or speak to them: passions, desires, resolutions, yearnings, fantasies, volitions, thoughts, reasonings, all of which are called, in a simplifying manner, soul, as though there were already certainly a unity here. Human beings must exercise this government over themselves, precisely because, when obeying those forces, it is not possible to achieve everything at the same time; indeed, in most cases it is possible to achieve only one thing. But who will steer human beings toward this one thing if not they themselves?

    In dealing with their own existence, therefore, human beings must first of all deal with their soul, that field of multiple forces, in which and through which they must find their bearings, in order to be in this or that existential condition. But dealing with their soul in this manner is a creative form of governing, as is manifest in its paradigmatic mode. Here human beings, according to Plato’s description of this paradigmatic mode (which will be discussed in greater detail later in the book),⁴ go about the work of the soul (psyches ergon), i.e., they engage in an activity that is, if we are permitted the word, entirely soul-like, insofar as it creates the soul, i.e., the governing work called soul. For this activity aims at really bringing into being, for the first time, a soul out of the multiplicity of those forces in human beings that pull them and speak to them. This soul, which is supposed to be the aim of the activity in question, is to be understood as a faculty that, once it is acquired by being exercised, enables human beings to be themselves, so that they govern—kratein is Plato’s word⁵—the forces that exist in them, and not the other way around.

    All that is meant by the word human being is creative politics. Its beginnings are a beginning toward humanity. To evoke this truth is the purpose of this book.

    At the Start

    We must distinguish between a beginning [Anfang] and a start [Beginn]. First, we must distinguish them according to cosmological knowledge, as expressed for instance in the Dao De Jing: All things arose from it [the great Tao/Way], but it is not their originator. . . . The Tao protects and nurtures all things but does not claim to be their master¹ And, second, we must distinguish them by emphasizing the atemporal meaning of the word start, since this word is intended to designate precisely that start which creates time—the sequence denoted by it—but

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1