Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Language and Value: ProtoSociology Volume 31
Language and Value: ProtoSociology Volume 31
Language and Value: ProtoSociology Volume 31
Ebook377 pages5 hours

Language and Value: ProtoSociology Volume 31

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

This volume represents the first substantial collaborative work from Chinese and Western scholars on philosophy of language. We believe that recent developments in the Anglo-American philosophy and Chinese philosophy of language not only suggest a tableau of shared problems, but also a number of similar methods and goals. It is the goal of this volume to juxtapose these recent philosophical developments to illustrate the similarities between the traditions, but also to spur common dialogue and hopefully efforts to jointly engage shared philosophical problems.
The issues engaged range from the role of cultural and biological factors in linguistic competence and language use, to figurative speech in different languages, the comparative study of work in semantics and philosophy, and the role of language in establishing the legal and ethical norms and values.
Content and abstracts: www.protosociology.de
LanguageEnglish
Release dateSep 17, 2015
ISBN9783739258904
Language and Value: ProtoSociology Volume 31
Author

Yi Jiang

Professor Jiang Yi of the School of Philosophy and Sociology, at Beijing Normal University, is one of most distinguished scholars in analytic philosophy and philosophy of language in China. He has published several books in Chinese on Wittgenstein and analytic philosophy. His interests are analytic philosophy, philosophy of language and Wittgenstein.

Related to Language and Value

Titles in the series (6)

View More

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Language and Value

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Language and Value - Yi Jiang

    ProtoSociology

    An International Journal of Interdisciplinary Research

    Volume 31, 2014

    Language and Value

    Edited by Yi Jiang and Ernie Lepore

    CONTENTS

    Introduction

    Ernest Lepore and Yi Jiang

    SEMANTICS AND ONTOLOGY

    The Relation of Language to Value

    Jiang Yi

    Refutation of the Semantic Argument against Descriptivism

    Chen Bo

    Semantics for Nominalists

    Samuel Cumming

    Semantic Minimalism and Presupposition

    Adam Sennet

    Compositionality and Understanding

    Fei YuGuo

    Values Reduced to Facts: Naturalism without Fallacy

    Zhu Zhifang

    WORD MEANING, METAPHER, AND TRUTH

    Philosophical Investigations into Figurative Speech Metaphor and Irony

    Ernie Lepore and Matthew Stone

    Norms of Word Meaning Litigation

    Peter Ludlow

    The Inconsistency of the Identity Thesis

    Christopher Hom and Robert May

    Describing I-junction

    Paul M. Pietroski

    Predicates of Taste and Relativism about Truth

    Barry C. Smith

    Mood, Force and Truth

    William B. Starr

    A Semiotic Understanding of Thick Terms

    Aihua Wang

    FEATURES OF CHINA’S ANALYTICAL PHILOSOPHY

    An Echo of the Classical Analytic Philosophy of Language from China: the Post-analytic Philosophy of Language

    Guanlian Qian

    The Chinese Language and the Value of Truth-seeking: Universality of Metaphysical Thought and Pre-Qin Mingjia’s Philosophy of Language

    Limin Liu

    Mthat and Metaphor of Love in Classical Chinese Poetry

    Ying Zhang

    On ProtoSociology

    Digital Volumes available

    INTRODUCTION

    Ernest Lepore and Yi Jiang

    It is our great pleasure to introduce this volume of essays, which represent (in our modest opinion) the beginning of an era of Chinese and English language philosophical cooperation. The Chinese philosophical tradition and the Western philosophical tradition (starting with the Ancient Greeks) have often been considered orthogonal to each other—two ships passing in the night without much to say to each other. Whatever the merits of this thesis, we believe that recent developments in the Anglo-American philosophy and Chinese philosophy of language not only suggest a tableau of shared problems, but also a number of similar methods and goals. It is the goal of this volume to juxtapose these recent philosophical developments to illustrate the similarities between the traditions, but also to spur common dialogue and hopefully efforts to jointly engage shared philosophical problems.

    The essays in this volume (by contributors from the United States, Great Britain, Australia and China) address issues about language and value from philosophical perspectives that overlap in surprising ways. The issues engaged range from the role of cultural and biological factors in linguistic competence and language use, to figurative speech in different languages, the comparative study of work in semantics and philosophy, and the role of language in establishing the legal and ethical norms and values.

    This volume represents the first substantial collaborative work from Chinese and Western scholars on philosophy of language. Although there has previously been some collaboration between Chinese and English language academics, there has never been a contemporary philosophical collection of this design, where each essay appears in both Chinese and English, and the two versions are presented side by side. It is our hope that by this endeavor we will be able to encourage greater collaborations among scholars both in China and in the English-speaking world. Our mission is to provide a bridge between traditions, leading to mutual understanding, philosophical collaboration, and ultimately a level of philosophical progress that could not be achieved were we working separately. We believe there is much to be gained by our working together in such an enterprise.

    To this end, in addition to assembling the essays in this volume, we paired each contributor from China with an English speaking philosopher; the paired philosophers read, edited and commented on each others work. The philosophers were thus able to rewrite their papers with the help of advice from a fresh perspective. In some cases this led to the introduction of arguments and moves that had not previously been considered; in other cases it led to a better handle on how the ideas should be presented—it opened the ideas to a broader philosophical audience. We believe that this has made for a compelling, globally accessible, and yes revolutionary new body of philosophical work.

    The Chinese philosophers who have contributed represent a broad spectrum of the current academic world in China.

    CHEN Bo is a professor of Philosophy at Peking University. He is one of most distinguished scholars in logic and analytic philosophy in China. He has published several essays in top journals in A&HCI list. His interests are philosophy of logic, Quine’s philosophy, and philosophy of language.

    Professor JIANG Yi of the School of Philosophy and Sociology, at Beijing Normal University, is one of most distinguished scholars in analytic philosophy and philosophy of language in China. He has published several books in Chinese on Wittgenstein and analytic philosophy. His interests are analytic philosophy, philosophy of language and Wittgenstein.

    Professor LIU Limin, of School of Foreign Languages, is at Sichuan University. His interests are philosophy of language and linguistics.

    Professor QIAN Guanlian, of Guangdong University of Foreign Studies, has for some time now been a important and distinguished scholars in pragmatics and the philosophy of language. He has published several books in Chinese on pragmatics.

    YUGUO Fei, is a member of the Philosophy of Department at Yunnan University in Kunming. He received his PhD from Wuhan University, and his chief interests include logic and philosophy of language.

    WANG Aihua is an Associate Professor of School of Foreign Language, at the University of Electronic Science and Technology of China in Chengdu. Her interests are also in pragmatics and philosophy of language.

    ZHANG Ying, of Philosophy Department, at Huazhong University of Science and Technology, received her PhD from Sun Yat-sen University. She was a visiting professor at Rutgers for two years, and her chiefs interests are the philosophy of language, logic and pragmatics.

    Lastly, Professor ZHU Zhifang, of Philosophy Department, at Wuhan University. He is one of more distinguished scholars in analytic philosophy and logic in China. He has published several books and essays in logic and philosophy of language. His interests are logic, philosophy of language and semiotics. From the English speaking community our volume includes previously unpublished papers by a number of distinguished theorists of language.

    Adam SENNET, an Associate Professor, Dept. of Philosophy, UC Davis, specializes in the philosophy of language and has published papers in Mind and Language, Philosophical Studies, and the Journal of Philosophical Logic.

    Samuel CUMMING, an Assistant Professor of Philosophy, UCLA, has interests in the philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, semantics and pragmatics.

    Peter LUDLOW is Professor of Philosophy at Northwestern University. He has published on topics ranging from the philosophy of linguistics to the metaphysics of time. His current interests include the dynamics of communication (including the dynamics of the lexicon) and the optimization of group knowledge in adversarial environments.

    Christopher HOM, Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Texas Tech University. He earned his PhD from the University of California, Irvine (LPS). His research interests are in philosophy of language, metaethics, and philosophy of race. He has published articles on racial slurs and normative language generally.

    Paul PIETROSKI, Professor of Linguistics and Professor of Philosophy, University of Maryland. His research interests are focused on how linguistic meaning is related to human psychology.

    Robert MAY is Distinguished Professor of Philosophy and Linguistics at the University of California, Davis. He is the author of Logical Form: Its Structure and Derivation,and with Robert Fiengo of Anaphora and Identity and De Lingua Belief. He is well-known for his work in the syntax and semantics of natural language, especially on natural language quantification, and has written extensively on Frege, along with other topics in philosophy of language and philosophy of logic.

    William STARR, Assistant Professor at the Sage School of Philosophy, Cornell University. His research is on communication and cognition, drawing on ideas across philosophy, linguistics, logic, artificial intelligence and psychology. His published work explores these themes through various linguistic phenomena including conditionals, questions, imperatives, modality and speech acts.

    Matthew STONE completed his Ph.D. in the Computer and Information Science Department at the University of Pennsylvania in 1998. Since then he has had an appointment in the Computer Science Department and Center for Cognitive Science at Rutgers, the State University of New Jersey. Stone has had visiting positions at the University of Edinburgh and the Universität Potsdam. He works on problems of meaning in human-human and human-computer conversation.

    Barry C SMITH is a Professor of Philosophy and Director of the Institute of Philosophy in the School of Advanced Study, University of London, where he co-directs the Centre for the Study of the Senses. He has written mostly on the philosophy of mind and language, on the topics of self-knowledge and our knowledge of language. He co-edited The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language (2006) with Ernest Lepore. Following his 2007 collection, Questions of Taste—the philosophy of wine (Oxford University Press), he began working with psychologists, neurologists and neuroscientists on flavour perception and is now the co-organiser of an international research project on the Nature of Taste. He has been a Visiting Professor at the University of California at Berkeley and at the Ecole Normale Supèriere, and was the writer and presenter of the BBC World Service radio series, The Mysteries of the Brain.

    Ernest LEPORE is the Director of the Center for Cognitive Science at Rutgers University and a Professor of philosophy. His chief interests are philosophy of language and philosophy of mind.

    I. Semantics and Ontology

    THE RELATION OF LANGUAGE TO VALUE

    Jiang Yi

    Abstract

    How does language relate to value? Why do we concern with the relation up to now? I will analyze the background of increasing interests in the relation of language to value in contemporary philosophy of language, provided with ideas that language has meaning with intention which determines the way of acts in relation with values in societies, and that, when we consider the value in language, we are searching for consequences of our speech acts for final goals of language.

    In 1836 Alexander Bryan Johnson (1786–1867), so-called a philosophical banker, published his unrecognized book, A Treaties on Language, which was the continuity of his first writing, Philosophy of Human Knowledge in 1828. In the book he committed the meaning of words as reminder of human knowledge which seems to be seen to have anticipated the thrust of logical positivism, at least in arguing that misunderstandings of how language operates bedevil philosophical questions, and theories of modern linguistics. After a century of his death a conference on the life and works of Johnson was held in Utica in1967. The proceedings of the conference was published in 1970, entitled Language and Value, in which he was interpreted as a generalist as a banker, businessman, essayist, satirist, and philosopher. The title of the proceedings hints his binary character of banker and philosopher. This might be the first time to relate language to value, though not in professional philosophy.

    In 2002 Diana Mary Kilpert published her Language and Value: The Place of Evaluation in Linguistic Theory, in which she tries to address the evaluation in language studies. But it is just in linguistic sense that we can evaluate languages in our social activities. Much writings on languages of evaluation from different perspectives, such as sociological and political, appeared recently. Most of them are concerned with applications of the theory of evaluation in language rather than the theory itself. Philosophers of language would, in contrast, consider the relation of language to value, concentrating on value elements of language in use, not evaluation in language. Thus we should clarify firstly some distinctions among those concepts which are confused with in our discourse of the relation of language to value.

    The Pragmatic are concerned mostly with terms which are full in evaluation and appraisal. Thus they discuss implications of those terms in use, not the meaning of such a term in its self. So in this sense there is difference between language of evaluation and evaluation of language, which makes our discussion clearer in clarification of the relation of language to value. The difference is that, while talking in the language of evaluation, we are not evaluating the language but the implications of language in which we express our intention to evaluate. Further on, even if we acknowledge the difference of the two we have to know that we could not understand the terms with speaker’s intentions of evaluation without any knowledge of language itself. So we have to know what makes us to use the language of evaluation to appraise what we want to do so.

    Philosophers of language do not want to talk about the value or evaluation of language but the correlation of language to value which is central to discussion of implication of languages in use. The term, value, here refers to varieties of implicatures of language when we use them to demonstrate and fulfill our goals for expressions. The question why language is concerned with value is involved in most flourished discussions on Oxford Ordinary Philosophy since 1950s. Stanley Cavell’s well-known paper, Must we mean what we say, in 1957 explained the reason why we should not assert what we know when we talk about what we might think we know. He said:

    The nature of the Oxford philosopher’s question, and the nature of his conception of philosophy, can be brought out if we turn the question upon itself, and thus remind ourselves of when it is we need to remind ourselves of what we should say when. Our question then becomes: When should we ask ourselves when we should (and should not) say The x is F in order to find out what an F(x) is? The answer suggested is: When you have to.¹

    That you have to means that there is something tacit you would know already when you say in the ordinary language. And this is a sense in which we have to deal with significance of words in the language.

    Charles Travis in his paper, Pragmatics, provided us with a pragmatic view which is opposite to a semantic one. The pragmatic view is that it is intrinsically part of what expressions of English mean that any English sentence may, on one speaking of it or another, have any of indefinitely many different truth conditions, and that any English expression may, meaning what it does, make any of many different contributions to truth conditions of wholes in which it figures as a part.² It is involved in discussion of implicature of words in utterances when we use them to mean something else that some problems on intensionality and propositional attitudes would be part of being central to the philosophy of language.

    Scott Soames in his recent book, What is Meaning, challenges the traditional theory of propositions from Frege and Russell by providing a new view which is explained as being cognitive relative. In this view propositions are take to be cognitive-event types, provided that one’s acquaintance with and knowledge of propositions is acquaintance with and knowledge of events of one’s cognitive life. He says:

    Propositions, as I understand them, can play the roles for which they are needed in semantics, pragmatics, and other areas of philosophy. However, they are not the source of that which is representational in mind and language. Sentences, utterances, and mental states are not representational because of the relations they bear to inherently representational propositions. Rather, propositions are representational because of the relations they bear to inherently representational mental states and cognitive acts of agents.³

    As we know, mental states and cognitive acts of agents are intention-directed which relate to the value relations of speakers and hearers. In this sense Soames locates meaning in thought, perception, and the cognitive acts of agents.

    Ernie Lepore and Barry Loewer in their new book, Meaning, Mind and Matter, defended and expanded three views in the philosophy of language for several decades. They provided a much strong argument for the irreducibility of the mental to the physical. According to it the global supervenience does not require the existence of strict laws connecting physical with mental properties or that mental properties are identical to physical properties.⁴ In contrast,

    The interesting point for us is that what will happen, or if we allow probabilities over micro histories, the probabilities of what will happen are given by adding one or the other decision to the state that is most similar to the actual state that contains the brain state corresponding to the decision. So the reason we are interested in evaluating counterfactuals along Lewisian lines is that conditionals so evaluated contain information about the likely results of our decisions and this information is enormously important to our getting what we want.

    It seems that the two philosophers would provide us with more interesting explanations of the gap in the mental and the physical. If we understand well the motives of the authors in their book, there will be some intentions in their explanations to clarify the extra significance of the mental a priori to the physical. And if we understand well the significance, we can locate it to our society, though it is not immediate in society.

    All above demonstrate that philosophers of language began to pay much attention to the relevance of language to value in which the intention such as propositional attitudes and other properties of utterances in our language is expressed vaguely or explicitly. But the questions remain: how does language relate to value? And, why we concern with such a relation up to now?

    First of all, we should make clear on the issue by discussing the relevance of language to the problem of value. As we mentioned the term value here is involved in the significance of language we use in society. The problem of value in the philosophy of language has been considered as a part of pragmatics when we use language to express our intentions, and evaluate consequences of speakers’ utterances on hearers and actions. There is, however, a substantial part in the problem of value in the philosophy of language. According to the previous consideration the problem and language might be distinct each other. So, we are expressing our intentions in language when we talk about the problem in the philosophy of language. But it is, I would say, on a wrong way. We are not expressing our intentions in language when we talk about the problem. We are communicating each other by language in which our intentions are expressed and understood. In this sense the value of language is shown or illuminated implicitly by utterances in language. In other words, speaking strictly, language is marked by value.

    From this start point we can argue that language has meaning with intention which determines the way of acts in relation with values in societies, and that, when we consider the value in language, we are searching for consequences of our speech acts in advance for final goals of language.

    The meaning of words has been considered as consisting of intentions the speaker intends to express in those words. From Frege on the problem of meaning of words is a puzzle, for not any single theory of meaning could settle down the puzzle for a century. The main reason I think is that we almost forgot the nature of language as the mark of human value. We are content to think language as an entity which bears varieties of function in different theories. However, language is not an entity which we can attribute properties to. Language should be thought of as a process which develops smoothly our intentions determining the way of acts we do in language. It is indispensable that the way of acts in language is shown in our society in which the function of language can be fulfilled with intentions speakers express in language.

    References

    S. Cavell, 1976, Must We Mean What We Say, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    B. Hale & C. Wright, ed.,1997, A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Oxford and New York: Blackwell.

    E. Lepore & B. Loewer, 2011, Meaning, Mind ,& Matter, Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press

    S. Soames, 2010,What is Meaning, Princeton: Princeton University Press.


    1 S. Cavell, Must We Mean What We Say, Cambridge University Press, 1976, p.21.

    2 C. Travis, Pragmatics, in B. Hale & C. Wright (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Language, Blackwell, 1997, p.87.

    3 S. Soames, What is Meaning, Princeton University Press, 2010, p.7.

    4 E. Lepore & B. Loewer, Meaning, Mind ,& Matter, Oxford University Press, 2011, p.7.

    5 Ibid, pp.231–232.

    REFUTATION OF THE SEMANTIC ARGUMENT AGAINST DESCRIPTIVISM

    Chen Bo

    Abstract

    There are two problematic assumptions in Kripke’s semantic argument against descriptivism. Assumption 1 is that the referential relation between a name and its bearer is only a metaphysical relation between language and the world; it has nothing to do with our public linguistic practice. Assumption 2 is that if name N has its meaning and the meaning is given by one description or a cluster of descriptions, the description(s) should supply the necessary and sufficient condition for determining what N designates; it is possible for us to find out such a condition for fixing the referent of N. Emphasizing the sociality, conventionality and historicity of language and meaning, this paper criticizes Assumption 1 and Assumption 2, and concludes that Kripke’s semantic argument fails.

    1. Opening

    To refute descriptivism, Kripke reformulates its cluster version refined by Wittgenstein and Searle. For him, cluster-descriptivism consists of six theses, in which theses (1), (3) and (4) are the targets of his semantic argument:

    (1) To every name or designating expression ‘X’, there corresponds a cluster of properties, namely the family of those properties φ such that [the speaker] A believes ‘φX’.

    (3) If most, or a weighted most, of the j’s are satisfied by one unique object γ, then γ is the referent of ‘X’.

    (4) If the vote yields no unique object, ‘X’ does not refer.

    In my view, Kripke’s semantic argument can be summarized as follows.

    If descriptivism is correct, that is, name N is exactly synonymous with one description or a cluster of descriptions, then, the meaning⁷ of N should be the necessary and sufficient condition for determining what N designates. In other words, if an object satisfies the corresponding description(s), it is the semantic reference of N (i.e., the sufficiency of meaning of N for fixing the referent of N); if an object does not satisfy the description(s), it is not the semantic reference of N (i.e., the necessity of meaning of N for fixing the referent of N). However, for a great number of names it is not the case that the corresponding description(s) constitutes the necessary and sufficient condition for identifying their references. So descriptivism gets the semantic facts wrong.⁸

    This argument can be reformulated more simply as follows, in which ‘P1’ for premise 1, ‘C’ for the conclusion, ‘N’ stand for a name, and so forth.

    For this argument, I accept P2, but I reject P1; so I do not accept conclusion C. I think that there are two problematic assumptions in the argument:

    Assumption 1 (A1 for short): The referential relation between a name (or a description) and its bearer is strictly ‘objective’ or ‘metaphysical’; in particular, it is not sensitive to the facts about our linguistic community; in other words, it has nothing to do with our linguistic community.

    I will argue that A1 is wrong, because the referential relation between a name (or a description) and its bearer is actually a social relation, which concerns three elements, i.e. the name (or a description), the object, and our linguistic community. What a name (or a description) designates depends on what our linguistic community uses the name (or a description) to designate.

    Assumption 2 (A2 for short): If name N has its meaning and the meaning is given by one description or a cluster of descriptions, the corresponding description(s) should supply the necessary and sufficient condition for determining what N designates. Also, it is possible for us to find out such a condition for fixing the referent of N.

    I will argue that A2 is wrong for three reasons: (a) A2 is a misunderstanding

    [Bedeutung] of a linguistic expression; in its narrow sense, ‘meaning’ only signifies to the sense of an expression, which could be understood and grasped by human minds. This paper only uses the word ‘meaning’ in its narrow sense.

    or distortion of traditional descriptivism. (b) We cannot require that a proper name is exactly synonymous with some description(s), and cannot ask the necessary and sufficient condition for fixing what the name designates, because there is no such condition at all. (c) When determining the referent of a name by means of the meaning of the name, we should consider not only the factual satisfaction relation between an object and some description(s), but also speakers’ intention, Network and Background, all of which together determine what a name designates.

    I will conclude that Kripke’s semantic argument fails.

    2. Exposing the Assumptions of the Semantic Argument

    2.1. Assumption 1

    Kripke tries to disprove thesis (3) of cluster-descriptivism by offering some counterexamples, for there can be situations in which the family φ of descriptions corresponding to a name N is actually satisfied by a unique object y, but y is still not the referent of N.

    Fictional Cases. Let us imagine a counterfactual situation. Gödel had a friend called ‘Schmidt’, who had actually proved the incompleteness of arithmetic. But Gödel somehow got hold of the manuscript and published it in his own name. Then Gödel achieved fame as ‘the man who discovered the incompleteness of arithmetic’. However, in fact, the semantic referent of that description is the man Schmidt. If ‘Gödel’ is synonymous with the description ‘the man who discovered the incompleteness of arithmetic’, does ‘Gödel’ change its referent into the man Schmidt? Kripke replies ‘No’, ‘Gödel’ still designates the person called ‘Gödel’ whereas ‘the man who discovered the incompleteness of arithmetic’ refers to the man Schmidt, because Schmidt is actually the person satisfying that description, and we make a mistake when using the description to refer to Gödel.

    Non-fictional Cases. It has been commonly believed that Peano is the man who discovered certain axioms which characterize the sequence of natural numbers. But actually it is Dedekind who discovered these axioms earlier; thus the description ‘the man who discovered certain axioms which characterize the sequence of natural numbers’ denotes Dedekind. Many people mistakenly regard Einstein as both the discoverer of the theory of relativity and the inventor of the atomic bomb. But actually it was not a single person but

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1