Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosopher Without Faith
Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosopher Without Faith
Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosopher Without Faith
Ebook173 pages2 hours

Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosopher Without Faith

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Professor Albérès in this well-ordered volume traces through successive works the elaboration of various concepts now linked to French Existentialism—anguish, nausea, hypocrisy, lucidity, consciousness, conformity, commitment, ethical values, situation, etc.
 
Translated from the French by Wade Baskin.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateNov 4, 2014
ISBN9781497675964
Jean-Paul Sartre: Philosopher Without Faith
Author

René Marill-Albérès

René Marill-Albérès (1921-1982) was a writer, speaker, editor, compiler and author of introductions. An authority on contemporary French literature and a novelist in his own right, Professor Albérès is eminently qualified to trace the literary development and relate the leading French intellectual’s fictional works to his philosophical and political writings. Professor Albérès has also published studies of Sartre and Unamuno.  

Related to Jean-Paul Sartre

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Jean-Paul Sartre

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Jean-Paul Sartre - René Marill-Albérès

    I. SYSTEM AND SCOPE

    A. POINTS OF DEPARTURE

    The painstaking analysis and logical systematization of man’s solitude, freedom, and responsibility, and the desire to probe the consequences of man’s independence and of his ultimate responsibility to himself—such are apparently the touchstones of the works which appeared between 1938 and 1946 and which made Jean-Paul Sartre a writer renowned throughout the world.

    Sartre’s views are not new to our age. It may well be that the salient characteristic of the twentieth century is the absence of a rigorous doctrine to explain and direct human life. Horror in the face of convention and of the revelation of man’s nakedness is found at the dawn of the century in Péguy as well as in Gide and Unamuno, and the human drama that Malraux and Camus subsequently lived through is also that of man confronted by his destiny.

    Nor is such an attitude essentially atheistic. To Bernanos also, man is free and responsible, and alone in the dark. The idea that the paths of our lives are not marked out but depend solely on us, that everything must forever be begun anew,¹ that there are no rules to govern our conduct and no systems to bring us stability and peace of mind, is in point of fact the hallmark of the literature of our time; and Christianity, through its most convincing and effective writers, views life not as an established order but as an adventure.

    The great doctrine of Progress which caught up in its wake such men as Lamartine and Hugo has lost its appeal. The harmonious syntheses of Classicism and the great systems of the Enlightenment belong to the past.

    The result is that man, cut off from the support of ready-made doctrines in which he no longer believes, is aware of his solitude. And in his loneliness his anxiety mounts as he becomes aware of his freedom and his responsibility. At the heart of the works of Bernanos, Malraux, Graham Greene, and Camus is the apparently contradictory and yet ineluctable relation of solitude to responsibility. The paradoxical relation has been labeled the tragic element, anguish, fate, and even absurdity. Man no longer believes in pat explanations and conventional, expedient rules for living, and yet the absence of external props and restraints does not eliminate his responsibility. On the contrary, recognition of his responsibility increases his anguish, with the result that the problem has finally invaded all literature and given it what is carelessly called a metaphysical aspect. This aspect is in fact moral.

    The moral problem is at the heart not only of Sartre’s writings but also of those of his predecessors and contemporaries.

    His originality, however, resides in the fact that he treats the problem systematically and philosophically. The most original characteristic of Sartre’s work seems at first glance to be the formulation in philosophical terms, and therefore the systematic formulation (to the extent that it is reduced to methodical postulates) of the great moral problem of the twentieth century: the anguish brought about by man’s responsibility in the absence of any restraint on the exercise of his responsibility.

    Man can not simply enjoy the existing world but must take a definite stand. This Sartre discovered and expressed in his most famous works, produced between 1938 and 1946, between Nausea and Roads to Freedom. It is the same necessity to act in the face of the world and the situations which it provides for us and imposes on us that Sartre has been interpreting since 1946 while changing from a psychological and moralistic writer to a political and social analyst. But this second period is also characterized by the formation of a school and by the publishing and editing of a monthly journal, Les Temps Modernes. If Sartre’s writings and pattern of living have taken a new tack since 1946, and if he has tended to become a cartoonist rather than a writer, the change was first imposed by his work as a moralist and by his talent as an artist.

    Until 1946 Sartre’s writings, though designed to serve as concrete illustrations of his philosophical system, are also prime examples of his art. His novels have a life and an atmosphere of their own; they have a literary existence which at first fails even to suggest that they illustrate a doctrine. Nausea at first seems to be an account of the boredom and obsessions of an isolated, disabused celibate living in a little town he despises. Certain episodes in The Wall and in Intimacy at first seem to be obliging descriptions of obscene and frivolous beings. The first volumes of Roads to Freedom at first seem to be a sympathetic satire on weary Frenchmen who in 1938 are waiting in the Parisian bistros for the war to begin.

    And certainly it is tempting to consider separately the fictional world that emerges in his early works, for it has a certain unity: trite urban scenes with nothing at the end of the avenues; ineffective but intelligent, and not wholly worthless characters without horizons and with stunted lives, always seen outside their working hours and often hard put to kill time. They are in general the human beings most frequently seen on the sidewalk or at the counter in a café but never in a group, whether in church, in the country, in the mountains, or in a foreign land; in short, the opposite of boy scouts, and prime examples of men who might be defined according to existential psychoanalysis by their fear of being dupes. As Sartre himself puts it:

    Well, my friend, she said, your lucidity always makes me laugh. You are so scared that you would give up the best deal in the world rather than risk self-deception.

    Yes, of course you’re right, said Mathieu. That’s what I’ve been telling you all along.²

    Sartre has been censured for depicting such situations, and sometimes a pharisaical element has entered into the criticism. But these situations are chosen for the very reason that they epitomize the rejection of the ineluctable responsibility which is imposed on man and which Camus and Malraux bring to the fore with more restrained lyricism. Mathieu in Roads to Freedom is indeed a man who eludes his responsibility. But it is precisely by refusing to assume it that he affirms it and proves its existence. It is through a sort of reduction to the absurd that Sartre tries to focus attention on human responsibility in beings who reject it. Those who accept it prove nothing; they only affirm their belief in their destiny. Sartre pretends to prove the existence of human responsibility by pointing up its absence or its suppression among those who slight it. That he may show partiality and undue concern in depicting inaction is something else, and this brings up the eternal problem of the writer who in depicting Evil and lust so as to make them abhorrent may be a victim of his own game. This criticism has actually been directed against both Racine and Mauriac.

    Man’s moral solitude, which brings into focus his inevitable responsibility, is not the sole concern of other writers who have examined and protested man’s fate. In Camus there is a sort of cosmic, Mediterranean brotherhood which reasserts the mating of man and the world; in Malraux, a dialog with eternity; and in Bernanos, of course, an almost carnal union between God and Satan. Still, for these three writers the central problem is the same as for Sartre, man’s responsibility in the face of his destiny.

    But one can find in Sartre no cosmic vision, no suggestion of the human adventure, and of course no faith. Man is imprisoned in the human consciousness, alienated from the earth, landscapes, the cosmos. Everything that can bring about a harmonious relation is obviously revealed through man’s consciousness; since this fact serves as his philosophical point of departure, Sartre limits himself to describing the human consciousness. Fugitive landscapes appear as an object of consciousness; no animistic illusion gives them life. God himself can be discussed in this life only as an object of human consciousness, and since it can not wholly conceive of Him and define Him, Sartre concludes that He does not exist. That is why his universe is limited to consciousness.

    His fictional world is narrow and restricted like that of novelists and classic dramatists concerned solely with the study of the emotions; that is why it is both deadening and dense.

    In this sense Sartre allies himself with moralists and is a moralist, that is, a writer who makes it his sole task to observe, describe, and if need be to judge human conduct. He has no concern and apparently not even any love for anything other than man—neither nature nor animals nor physical life nor the universe. His only universe is man, and even more specifically the conscious, adult man inured to life and capable of formulating its problems; the child who appears in Roads to Freedom³ does not belong to his universe, and when he forces himself into it, Mathieu is surprised:

    Little Pablo looked at him. There he stood, tiny and puzzled; but behind the dull humors that filled his sockets lurked a greedy little consciousness.

    You know what I dreamed? asked Pablo.

    What?

    I dreamed that I was a feather.

    That figures, Mathieu thought.

    Sartre’s vision is limited to man, and to man wrapped up in his own human problems. He does not try to relate man to other, more imposing realities that surround him, as do Giraudoux, Claudel, and Malraux with their cosmic vision. In his view man is independent, given; man is of interest to him only when separated from other things, real or hypothetical, through philosophical reflection. In the strictly human domain which he has appropriated, Sartre refuses to give in to certain temptations, such as the cultivation of the picturesque side of people or a predilection for romantic adventures. There are few events in the stories that he relates, and these events are always psychological and moral events.

    That is why, however novel his style may have appeared when given the public’s stamp of approval, he has done nothing more than adopt the attitude and angle of vision of the French moralists. He has less gentleness and breadth than Montaigne, less charm than La Bruyère, less concern for grandeur that Stendhal, and perhaps much less than La Rochefoucauld or Pascal. Like La Rochefoucauld, he analyzes human conduct in order to fashion a system for judging it. Like Pascal he insists on the justification or nonjustification of acts and poses the essential problem of their value when judged in terms of man’s fate rigidly and harshly defined.

    Nevertheless, there is no contradiction in the fact that a moralist can be accused of immorality. Observing, describing, and passing judgment on man do not necessarily imply judging him according to criteria labeled moral by society. As a matter of fact, the charge of immorality that has frequently been made against Sartre can be understood only in the light of the three premises on which it is grounded.

    First, to the extent that he observes and analyzes man, Sartre gives an account of the whole human reality and even of the part that modesty conceals. This realism may be shocking, but Sartre’s defense is that he is exercising his privilege as a scientific observer and that as a physician of the soul he is compelled to overlook nothing and to surprise man in every possible posture in his search for absolute truth. But beyond this, it has been charged that in his concern

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1