Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library)
The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library)
The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library)
Ebook161 pages1 hour

The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library)

Rating: 1 out of 5 stars

1/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

This edition includes a modern introduction and a list of suggested further reading.  We have reached the end of art, states Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel in The Philosophy of Art. Hegel charts the progression of art in order to show how it reached its full and final development. But that does not mean that art is dead to us-far from it. Hegel argues for the significance of the philosophy of art, which for him ranks higher than the study of nature in terms of aiding our understanding of reality. Accompanying Hegel's overview of his science of aesthetics are a laudatory introduction by the prominent nineteenth-century scholar and translator W. Hastie and an extensive elaboration of Hegel's ideas by his student C. L. Michelet.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateMar 13, 2012
ISBN9781411466418
The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library)
Author

G. W. F. Hegel

G. W. F. Hegel (1770–1831) is one of the most significant thinkers in the history of philosophy. He is the author of several influential works, including The Science of Logic.

Read more from G. W. F. Hegel

Related to The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library)

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library)

Rating: 1 out of 5 stars
1/5

1 rating0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    The Philosophy of Art (Barnes & Noble Digital Library) - G. W. F. Hegel

    TRANSLATOR’S PREFACE

    IN ENGLAND, THE PHILOSOPHY OF ART HAS BEEN THE LEAST successfully cultivated of all the departments of speculative science. The age of the Reformation was too intent upon its immediate tasks, and too completely absorbed in its great creations, to pause reflectively over the modes of its own artistic working. After a period of uncertain movement and decaying power, the acute and versatile understanding of the eighteenth century, in reviewing its inheritance from the past, did not overlook the productive activity of the emotional nature; but the criticism and speculation of the age of Enlightenment could not rise above its own peculiarly negative and analytical interest. Even the elegant refinement of Addison, the careful meditation of Sir Joshua Reynolds, and the youthful ingenuity of Burke, present but little theoretical insight, and still less appreciation of historical research. Their barren efforts had a natural reaction and counterpart in the mere psychological analysis of the Associationalists, which culminated in Scotland in the pragmatic School of Alison and Jeffrey. With the beginning of the nineteenth century, however, there arose, as in contrast, a deeper feeling for elemental and essential Beauty, born of strong ideal strivings and of tender poetic insight into the harmony and vitality of nature. And, in continuation of this new movement, our own age has been shewing a gratifying progress in the deepening and broadening of its speculative interest, with closer regard for scientific precision and completeness, and with marked freedom and independence in its appreciation and criticism of Art.

    This progress in the artistic insight and sympathy of our time, is, no doubt, largely due to the genius of Mr. Ruskin as an enthusiastic expounder of the work of art, especially in the forms of modern Painting and Architecture. And, notwithstanding the occasional divergence and eccentricity of his accompanying teaching, the force and fervour of his stimulus cannot be too gratefully acknowledged. But with all the earnestness and variety and eloquence of the fervid Apostle of the pre-Raphaelite revival, and with all his poetic spontaneousness and subtle charm of association, his thought is, at the best, still too fragmentary and unsystematised to sustain or direct the whole ideal interest of Art. It is just in this sphere, however, where they are so apt to be ignored, that the severity of philosophic discipline and the comprehensiveness of scientific method, are most required to give clear purpose and unity to contemporary effort. Nor, with all his depth and subtlety of feeling, his lofty moral purpose and the elevating glow of his imaginative ardour, can the æsthetic Naturalism of Mr. Ruskin, permanently satisfy the higher artistic aspiration of the time, or furnish an adequate foundation for a genuine Philosophy of Art. His affluence of pictorial expression, his intensity and vividness in detail and even his wealth of knowledge gained from close artistic observation, still leave many of the deeper questions untouched or undefined. Our age needs a doctrine of Art, that can at once recognise its own practical surroundings and problems, and accompany the whole range of its ideal interest through its deepest and to its

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1