Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)
Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)
Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)
Ebook183 pages2 hours

Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)

Rating: 3.5 out of 5 stars

3.5/5

()

Read preview

About this ebook

One of the most interesting features of A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge is the symbiosis between a radical empiricism and a bold and uncompromising idealism. An artful combination of analytical rigor and unfettered speculation, of crystal-like precision of language and winged metaphors or sparkling images, George Berkeleys work is essentially a God-centered philosophy that argues that something exists only insofar as it is perceived by the mind.
LanguageEnglish
Release dateSep 1, 2009
ISBN9781411431195
Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)
Author

George Berkeley

George Berkley (1685–1753) was an Irish philosopher who thrived during the 18th century’s Age of Enlightenment. Born in Ireland and educated at Kilkenny College and Trinity College, he earned both a bachelor’s and master’s degree before entering a career as a lecturer. Berkley’s first notable work as a writer was An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision published in 1709. Yet, his biggest successes came with A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge followed by Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous. Berkley’s best known for his Theory of Immaterialism and contributions to the British Empiricism movement.

Read more from George Berkeley

Related to Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)

Related ebooks

Philosophy For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading)

Rating: 3.520833377777778 out of 5 stars
3.5/5

72 ratings2 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

  • Rating: 5 out of 5 stars
    5/5
    Those familiar with Norton's series of critical editions might be startled by the layout of this volume; since the critical essays precede the text, instead of following behind at a properly obsequious distance. Please do not be enticed into following this format. Turn immediately to the Principles, for if you start with the critical material you will likely never reach the promised land. Berkeley had many original things to say, and he was gifted with an excellent prose style. Neither, unfortunately, was passed along to all of his commentators; although I did particularly enjoy the essay "The place of God in Berkeley's philosophy", by J. D. Mabbott.
  • Rating: 3 out of 5 stars
    3/5
    In his introduction, David Armstrong argues that Berkeley is studied because he was a trailblazer in philosophical thought, despite the fact that his assumptions are invalid. Berkeley actually made multiple attempts to convince others of his thesis, following this essay with a more casual style in his "Three Dialogues." I found Berkeley very difficult to read, mostly because the meaning of specific terms seems to shift throughout the argument. Perhaps better scholars than I are able to follow the flow. Nonetheless, I hold to the conviction that part of our advance in argument has come about through the use of more specific terms. The point with which I am most in agreement is more of an aside by Berkeley -- that man tends to over-complicate thinking and therefore loses the true meaning behind many things. Unfortunately, he seems to do the same within the pages after that point. Even if all of his points held, he results in a metaphyisical world that appears and disappears as we blink. Berkeley goes on to expound upon certain possibilities, such as God also perceiving that the objects exist and thus holding that they always exist.

Book preview

Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Barnes & Noble Library of Essential Reading) - George Berkeley

Table of Contents

Title Page

Copyright Page

Introduction

TO THE RIGHT HONOURABLE THOMAS, EARL OF PEMBROKE, &C.,

PREFACE

INTRODUCTION

OF THE PRINCIPLES OF HUMAN KNOWLEDGE

ENDNOTES

SUGGESTED READING

001002

Introduction and Suggested Reading Copyright © 2006 by Barnes & Noble Publishing, Inc.

Originally published in 1710

This edition published by Barnes & Noble Publishing, Inc.

All rights reserved. No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without written permission of the Publisher.

Cover Design by Stacey May

2006 Barnes & Noble Publishing, Inc.

ISBN 13: 978-0-7607-7769-5 ISBN 0-7607-7769-1

eISBN : 978-1-411-43119-5

Printed and bound in the United States of America

1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2

INTRODUCTION TO THE NEW EDITION

GEORGE Berkeley’s A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge brings forth one of the most perplexing philosophical systems of all times. Also known as immaterialism, this philosophy is centered on the notion that there is no such thing as matter, that the objects we see around us are nicely packed collections of ideas generated by God’s mind, and that, in general, what we call the world is just a subtle interplay between God’s mind and ours. The things we encounter in the world are either our constructs or God’s or both: in any case, they cannot exist unperceived, or un-thought of, by a mind. We ourselves exist in the same way in which characters in a story do: only insofar as there is someone (kind enough) to invent and tell the story. Controversial as this line of thought may seem, it has proven to be extremely influential over the centuries, not only in philosophy, but also in critical theory, literature, and cinematography. To give only a few examples, some of Jorge Luis Borges’ stories seem to be rigorously based on Berkeleian insights and so does the movie The Matrix or even some of Woody Allen’s films. Anyway, today, when we live half of our lives in virtual realities of some kind or other, and the real world tends to become more and more virtual, when we talk more and more of socially (or ideologically, culturally, politically) constructed objects and realities, reading A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge may well be part of a self-examination exercise.

George Berkeley was born near Kilkenny, Ireland, on 12 March 1685. Although his father was an Englishman from Staffordshire, throughout his life Berkeley considered himself Irish. He first attended Kilkenny College (formerly attended by Jonathan Swift, among others), and then when he was fifteen, he entered Trinity College Dublin, where he took his BA in 1704 and became a teaching fellow of the College in 1707. He was a lecturer in Greek, Hebrew, and Divinity, and, in some way or other, remained affiliated with the College until 1724, when he was appointed Dean of Derry. Berkeley published most of his major philosophical works at a relatively young age: An Essay Towards a New Theory of Vision (Dublin, 1709), A Treatise concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (Dublin, 1710), and Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous (London, 1713). Whereas in An Essay Berkley did not, for strategic reasons, deny the existence of matter as such, in Principles his immaterialism has already become a fully fledged philosophical doctrine. On its publication, Principles was not particularly well received in philosophical circles: Berkeley was laughed at, his thesis ridiculed, and one London physician overtly considered him mad. As the poet John Brown would later say, he was vanquished by a grin.¹ Because of this poor reception and at the same time because he aimed to reach an audience beyond the narrowly specialized circles of philosophers, Berkeley decided to translate the difficult content of the book into something more agreeable and easy to read. This is how the Three Dialogues was born. Although it did not present something necessarily new in terms of philosophical ideas and arguments, Three Dialogues is a major philosophical work in its own right, giving Berkeley a prominent place in the grand tradition of the Platonic dialogue and rendering him as one of the most gifted masters of the English language. At the same time, Berkeley’s decision to write for a considerably wider audience is highly indicative of a certain tendency of his (which was increasingly more visible as the years passed) to conceive of his philosophical mission not in purely academic terms, but as something that has to be deeply useful for people’s lives, for their well being and sense of self-realization. In other words, Berkeley’s was a shift toward philosophy as a way of life, as something that is not to remain a dead letter and empty scholarship, but has to result in an existential transformation to occur in people, in their ways of living and of thinking.

Since early adulthood, Berkeley had taken the dictum think with the learned, and speak with the vulgar as one of his precious maxims, but as he grew older he became more and more involved in projects in which his philosophical idealism came to be intertwined, in a highly sophisticated manner, with a certain social idealism. One of these projects was the so-called Bermuda project. In 1724 Berkeley published A Proposal for the better Supplying of Churches in our Foreign Plantations in which he advanced the idea of a theology college to be founded in the islands of Bermuda for the children of the European colonists and of the savage Indians. The college was designed to produce clergymen who would propagate the Gospel in the New World and provide spiritual guidance to both the colonists and—more importantly—to the native Indians, who would thus be brought to Christianity. Berkeley’s project has all the characteristics of an educational utopia: situated in a paradisiacal natural environment, his school was to be an ideal community of philosophers and scholars, dedicated to learning and complex studies, a school whose only aim was to preserve and convey the noblest values and virtues of humankind. Berkeley himself was to be the head of this utopian school; infected with his enthusiasm, some of the Fellows of Trinity College even enlisted as faculty. To speed things up, Berkeley sailed for America and spent some three years (1728-1731) in Newport, Rhode Island, making various preparations and waiting for the necessary funds from England. Money never came and the project gloriously failed, but Berkeley made excellent use of his American sojourn, writing—among other things—Alciphron (1732), a series of philosophical dialogues designed as an Apology for the Christian Religion. After his educational project failed, Berkeley returned to Europe and in 1734 he was appointed Bishop of Cloyne, Ireland.

In 1744 he published Siris. A Chain of Philosophical Inquiries Concerning the Virtues of Tar-Water. This book (today passed over in silence by most commentators) was definitely, in his lifetime, a best seller, with five editions in Dublin and London within only one year. The book is about nothing else but a universal medicine: marked by the terrible famine that hit Ireland in the early 1740s, the subsequent epidemic, and the acute lack of professional physicians in his diocese, Berkeley decides to stand the ridicule of embarking on yet another utopian project. He undertakes an ample historical-philosophical-theological journey to prove that tar-water (a quite inexpensive natural product) is capable of curing virtually all diseases and conferring upon the patient perfect health, a better life, and serenity of mind. The speculative (neo-Platonic and esoteric) arguments Berkeley employs in the process places him definitely in the alchemic tradition in which the philosopher’s stone was also known as medicina universalis. Just like the alchemists of the old times, and even using some of their cosmological and metaphysical speculations, Berkeley dreamed of finding a wonder solution for improving the well-being of people’s minds and bodies, transcending the narrow limits of humanity and, in some mysterious way, getting closer to the divine. Driven by grand social projects and dreams of human improvement, deeply marked by the utopian traditions of Europe, throughout his life Berkeley was, as his friend Jonathan Swift once remarked, an absolute philosopher with regard to money, titles, and power. The good Bishop died on 14 January 1753 in Oxford.

Principles, as we have it, is in fact the first part of a larger project: a second part was to deal with the being of a God & the freedom of Man, and a third part was to be about natural philosophy; neither of which was completed. Even if Principles is dedicated to the process through which human knowledge is being constituted, the book is saturated with theological issues. For this philosophy is essentially a God-centered philosophy: no matter the specific subject matter (ethics, political philosophy, economics) Berkeley deals with, sooner or later God will show up and firmly reassert his central position in the general scheme of things. One of the most interesting features of Berkeley’s philosophical style is precisely the symbiosis between a radical empiricism, expressing itself through an elegant and rigorous literary form, on the one hand, and a bold and uncompromising idealism in the tradition of Plato, Plotinus, Ficino, or the Cambridge Platonists, a highly speculative way of thinking (deeply rooted in Christian metaphysics), on the other hand. Extremely rarely in the history of Western philosophy has there been such an artful combination of analytical rigor and unfettered speculation, of crystal-like precision of language and winged metaphors or sparkling images.

Berkeley’s empiricism is centered on the notion that something exists only insofar as it is perceived by the mind ("esse is percipi ). The being of a thing is precisely its being perceived by a mind; in the absence of its perception, we cannot, properly speaking, say that something exists. The computer screen on which this text is being brought to life exists only insofar as I perceive it: in a certain way, it is my eyes that are conferring existence upon it. If I am to take the word existence seriously, I am forced to admit that in the absence of my sensorial experience of a certain object, that object would not exist for me—it would be a pure emptiness, the most absent of all objects. The world outside us grows incessantly under our eyes and under our fingertips, and because our ears pay attention to its sounds. We construct the world with our senses. Therefore, we can say we have an object only when we have an experience of it. Yet, it would be plainly absurd to say that objects cease to exist if we don’t pay attention to them anymore, if, say, we sleep, or travel, or if we die. Of course, they exist and they don’t care about our sleeping, or dying, or going away. They exist because, for Berkeley, in our absence they are perceived by God. The fact that, although I leave my room and go far away, things in my room continue to exist is, for Berkeley, a proof that God exists. In other words, if the principle to be is to be perceived" is valid, then there has to be a God. Thus, the existence of God is the necessary consequence of the empirical way of thinking on which Berkeley embarked when he adopted the "esse is percipi principle. In his own words, the things in the world so long as they are not actually perceived by me, or do not exist in my mind or that of any other created spirit, they must either have no existence at all, or else subsist in the mind of some Eternal Spirit" (§ 6). In a couple of famous limericks, Monsignor Ronald Knox (1888-1957) summed the argument up in a most entertaining manner:

There was a young man who said, "God

Must think it exceedingly odd

If he finds that this tree

Continues to be

When there’s no one about in the Quad."

Reply

Dear Sir:

Your astonishment’s odd:

I am always about in the Quad.

And that’s why the tree

Will continue to be,

Since observed by

Yours faithfully,

GOD²

Along the lines of this radical empiricism, Berkeley undertakes in Principles a rigorous analysis of our knowledge of the outside world, as well as of the complex of notions, concepts, and theories we customarily employ when talking about the world. He discovers, among other things, that since we never perceive matter as such (we perceive particular objects—objects of a certain shape, of a certain color, smell, or taste, but not matter as such), we cannot legitimately say that matter exists. Since we use a word about whose meaning we do not have any clear idea, Berkeley thus comes to say that "the very notion of what is called Matter or corporeal substance, involves a contradiction in it (§ 9). Not only is matter contradictory and unintelligible in theoretical terms, but for Berkeley the belief in the existence of Matter is simply dangerous: it gives birth to prejudices of all kinds, and has a very bad influence on people’s morals, worldviews, states of mind, and behaviors. The belief in the existence of matter is for him the source of evil in sciences and the arts, in society, church and morality: The existence of matter, or bodies unperceived, has not only been the main support of Atheists and Fatalists, but on the same principle doth Idolatry likewise in all its various forms depend"(§ 94). Matter is an unnecessary and harmful interposition between us and God; it doesn’t have any positive role at all, it only keep us away from the proximity of God. There is only one solution: immaterialism. Only the denial of the existence of matter could put an end to the fruitless philosophical disputes that have marked the history of humanity:

Matter being once expelled out of nature drags with it so many sceptical and impious notions, such an incredible number of disputes and puzzling questions, which have been thorns in the sides of the divines as well as philosophers, and made so much fruitless work for mankind. (§ 96)

Yet, if we expel matter out of nature, what is left? If there is no such thing as matter, what is it, then, that we experience in the outside world? It is God’s Discourse. The world is living word. In Principles, as well as in most of Berkeley’s other philosophical works, nature is seen as the visual language that God uses to speak with us. The things we see around us, their unfolding and succession, their changing into one another, are not meaningless occurrences, but they form a divine speech; they say something about the Author of Nature. In a strikingly similar fashion, long before Berkeley another Irish philosopher, Scotus Erigena, had said that there is nothing, in visible and corporeal things, that does not signify something incorporeal and invisible.³ In fact, when making such a statement Erigena himself relied massively on St. Paul’s Epistles, on St. Augustine, on the doctrine of Jesus Christ’s Incarnation, as well as on the Platonic way of thinking. With his theory of the world as God’s discourse, Berkeley thus joined a long tradition of thinking, one that held that

Enjoying the preview?
Page 1 of 1