Discover millions of ebooks, audiobooks, and so much more with a free trial

Only $11.99/month after trial. Cancel anytime.

Competition Policy and Price Fixing
Competition Policy and Price Fixing
Competition Policy and Price Fixing
Ebook818 pages26 hours

Competition Policy and Price Fixing

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars

()

Read preview

About this ebook

Throughout the world, the rule against price fixing is competition law's most important and least controversial prohibition. Yet there is far less consensus than meets the eye on what constitutes price fixing, and prevalent understandings conflict with the teachings of oligopoly theory that supposedly underlie modern competition policy.



Competition Policy and Price Fixing provides the needed analytical foundation. It offers a fresh, in-depth exploration of competition law's horizontal agreement requirement, presents a systematic analysis of how best to address the problem of coordinated oligopolistic price elevation, and compares the resulting direct approach to the orthodox prohibition.


In doing so, Louis Kaplow elaborates the relevant benefits and costs of potential solutions, investigates how coordinated price elevation is best detected in light of the error costs associated with different types of proof, and examines appropriate sanctions. Existing literature devotes remarkably little attention to these key subjects and instead concerns itself with limiting penalties to certain sorts of interfirm communications. Challenging conventional wisdom, Kaplow shows how this circumscribed view is less well grounded in the statutes, principles, and precedents of competition law than is a more direct, functional proscription. More important, by comparison to the communications-based prohibition, he explains how the direct approach targets situations that involve both greater social harm and less risk of chilling desirable behavior--and is also easier to apply.

LanguageEnglish
Release dateJun 30, 2013
ISBN9781400846078
Competition Policy and Price Fixing
Author

Louis Kaplow

Louis Kaplow is the Finn M. W. Caspersen and Household International Professor of Law and Economics at Harvard University and a Research Associate at the National Bureau of Economic Research. His books include The Theory of Taxation and Public Economics (Princeton).

Related to Competition Policy and Price Fixing

Related ebooks

Economics For You

View More

Related articles

Reviews for Competition Policy and Price Fixing

Rating: 0 out of 5 stars
0 ratings

0 ratings0 reviews

What did you think?

Tap to rate

Review must be at least 10 words

    Book preview

    Competition Policy and Price Fixing - Louis Kaplow

    Competition Policy and Price Fixing

    LOUIS KAPLOW

    Competition Policy and Price Fixing

    PRINCETON UNIVERSITY PRESS

    PRINCETON AND OXFORD

    Copyright © 2013 by Princeton University Press

    Published by Princeton University Press, 41 William Street, Princeton,

    New Jersey 08540

    In the United Kingdom: Princeton University Press, 6 Oxford Street,

    Woodstock, Oxfordshire OX20 1TW

    press.princeton.edu

    All Rights Reserved

    Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data

    Kaplow, Louis.

    Competition policy and price fixing / Louis Kaplow.

    pages cm

    Includes bibliographical references and index.

    ISBN 978-0-691-15862-4 (alk. paper)

    1. Competition—Government policy. 2. Antitrust law. 3. Price fixing. I. Title.

    HD41.K37 2013

    338.6'048–dc23        2012047888

    British Library Cataloging-in-Publication Data is available

    This book has been composed in Minion Pro

    Printed on acid-free paper. ∞

    Printed in the United States of America

    1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2

    For Irene, Leah, and Jody

    Summary of Contents

    Contents

    Preface

    Competition policy toward price fixing presents an unrecognized paradox. Commentators, competition agencies, and competition laws throughout the world unanimously condemn the practice, treating it as the field’s most important transgression, subject to its harshest sanctions. Yet further scrutiny reveals the prohibition’s definition to be incoherent, its practical reach uncertain, and its fit with fundamental economic principles obscure.

    Consensus has bred complacency. This book aims to be an antidote. Efficacy demands starting from scratch on two fronts: legal doctrine and economic policy analysis. Misunderstandings about the former constitute a straightjacket that has aborted progress on the latter. Accordingly, the plan of attack is to exhaustively examine the law so as to clear the way for a ground-up assessment of optimal competition policy toward price fixing.

    The root of the legal problem lies in competition law’s agreement requirement, which demarcates the domain of liability for price fixing. This precondition is examined from multiple perspectives, many underappreciated and some overlooked entirely: basic definitions of key terms, the concept of communications that many see as constitutive of a violation, statutory provisions, higher court interpretations, lower court practice, and basic oligopoly theory. Each inquiry undermines the conventionally endorsed view but is harmonious with the law’s reaching all successful coordinated price elevation by oligopolistic firms. This broad convergence should fully extinguish existing inhibitions and stimulate broader study, but it does not suffice to dictate policy because internal coherence does not guarantee optimal consequences for welfare.

    A systematic economic investigation of price-fixing policy has three elements: articulating the problem in terms of social welfare, assessing how to detect harmful behavior, and designing appropriate sanctions. Familiar static and often-ignored dynamic effects are examined, followed by the presentation of the appropriate framework for decision-making, a subject that has been largely neglected in the analysis of optimal enforcement quite generally as well as with regard to competition law. Detection is the most challenging element of the analysis. Various techniques are examined with a particular eye to their potential contribution to deterrence and also their tendency to generate false positives, the prospect of which chills desirable conduct. The appropriate magnitude and type of sanctions are determined by reference to the benefits and costs of penalizing underlying conduct.

    Finally, the emergent direct economic approach toward price fixing is compared to the traditionally favored proscription that focuses on particulars of firms’ communications—a subset of means to an end rather than the end itself. This familiar method is inferior on a priori grounds due to its formalistic nature and poor nexus with the social objective. Unfortunately, it is even worse. The commonly endorsed proscription constitutes a dominated strategy: Compared to the direct approach, it targets cases that generate relatively small deterrence gains and high chilling costs, while exonerating cases where the social danger is greatest and chilling costs are comparatively modest. In addition, contrary to widely held beliefs, it is more complex and costly to implement because it requires an additional, subtle inquiry with little evidence to guide it.

    Despite the power of the foregoing conclusions, this book should largely be understood as advancing conceptual understanding rather than specific policy prescriptions. First, it is unavoidably preliminary because it covers so much new territory—indeed, there is remarkably little subject matter overlap with most contemporary literature on the topic. Second, existing empirical knowledge provides limited illumination of many key issues. Third, optimal competition policy, particularly due to its economic complexity, is highly institutionally dependent, and institutions vary widely across the globe and even within some individual jurisdictions, notably, the United States. In sum, this book seeks to invigorate debate, redirect thinking, and guide future research, with the hope of improving the quality of subsequent discourse and, ultimately, of competition policy toward price fixing.

    • • •

    My interest in competition law and policy began as a student. During the course of my education, I have been tremendously lucky in my instructors and mentors: Mike Scherer, Mike Spence, Dick Caves, Mike Porter, and Phil Areeda. I have also benefited from my collaborations with co-authors—Phil Areeda and Aaron Edlin on Antitrust Analysis (a casebook for law students) and Carl Shapiro on Antitrust (a survey aimed at economists).

    From the outset of my academic career, the traditional treatment of the price-fixing prohibition has bothered me, and I have always found it difficult to teach material that I could not make sense of for myself. The exception in extant scholarship is Richard Posner’s 1969 article, followed by a chapter in his book on antitrust, which famously endorses a more economically based strategy for addressing oligopoly pricing. Although these writings have been widely cited, their substance has been largely ignored. The present investigation goes beyond Posner’s work and departs in many respects, which can hardly be surprising in light of the decades of theoretical and empirical work in industrial organization in the interim. Yet the spirit of his argument as well as some key insights provide invaluable illumination.

    In addition to my intellectual forebears, I wish to acknowledge the substantial support I have received over the years working on this project. For helpful discussions and comments, I am grateful to Jon Baker, Ryan Bubb, Aaron Edlin, Joe Harrington, Oliver Hart, Al Klevorick, Carl Shapiro, Steve Shavell, Kathy Spier, reviewers for the Princeton University Press, editors and referees at journals, and workshop and conference participants at Chicago, Columbia, Georgetown, Harvard, Michigan, NYU, Virginia, Yale, the Antitrust Division of the U.S. Department of Justice, Northwestern’s Searle Center Antitrust Economics and Competition Policy Conference, and the American Law and Economics Association Annual Meeting. Molly Eskridge, Matt Seccombe, and the team at Princeton University Press provided terrific administrative, editorial, and other assistance. I have also benefited substantially from the efforts of many talented research assistants (with apologies to any accidently omitted): Shobitha Bhat, Josh Branson, Jamison Davies, Danielle D’Onfro, Michael Doore, Ariel Fox, Joseph Gay, David Geiger, Barbara Glowacka, David Gottlieb, Jason Green-Lowe, Jesse Gurman, Kinga Guzdek, Anat Holtzman, James Ianelli, Daniel Jacobsen, Noam Lerer, Lauren Merrell, William Milliken, Soojin Nam, Balaji Narain, Max Nicholas, Maria Parra-Orlandoni, Robert Ritchie, Cody Rockey, Krysten Rosen, Michael Sabin, Dorothy Shapiro, and Joseph Vardner. Generous financial support was provided by Harvard Law School’s John M. Olin Center for Law, Economics, and Business; Harvard Law School; the Kaufmann Foundation; and the Leeds Research Fund. Finally, I wish to acknowledge that, in the course of writing this book, I published the following articles drawn from the manuscript: On the Meaning of Horizontal Agreements in Competition Law, California Law Review, vol. 99(3), 683–818 (2011); An Economic Approach to Price Fixing, Antitrust Law Journal, vol. 77(2), 343–449 (2011); and Direct versus Communications-Based Prohibitions on Price Fixing, Journal of Legal Analysis, vol. 3(2), 449–538 (2011).

    A brief note is in order regarding the extensive footnotes. Most of them present further analysis, qualifications, or illustrations that may be of great interest to some readers (perhaps those most inclined to disagree at various points) but would disrupt the flow if placed in the main body. A few serve to elaborate economic ideas, often subtleties, for those with less background. And, in the first part of the book, many contain significant legal detail, in some instances to document claims that may otherwise seem far-fetched or to illustrate the prominent endorsement of views that some might otherwise think to be straw men.

    Competition Policy and Price Fixing

    1

    Introduction

    The rule against price fixing is the least controversial prohibition in competition law throughout the world, and the practice is universally subject to the law’s harshest penalties. There is, however, far less consensus than meets the eye on what constitutes price fixing and on how legal regimes should determine its presence. More surprising, prevalent understandings are not grounded in oligopoly theory even though modern competition policy is widely taken to rest on economic substance rather than legal formalism.

    This book’s central aim is to provide an analytical foundation for designing policy toward coordinated price elevation in oligopolistic industries. In rough terms, the proper methodology is straightforward. First, one articulates the problem and undertakes welfare-based analysis to specify the benefits and costs of attempts to control it. Next, one examines how coordinated price elevation is best detected, attending to the error costs associated with different types of proof. Finally, one sets appropriate sanctions.

    These elements of a direct approach have received remarkably little attention in the literature. Instead, commentators, government agencies, and courts display some tendency to focus on penalizing certain sorts of interfirm communications that facilitate coordinated oligopoly pricing. Although such punishment has great value for unmasked cartels, systematic comparison with a more direct, functional approach reveals conventional means to be inferior and in important respects counterproductive in cases without smoking-gun evidence. In those settings, a direct approach dominates the conventionally favored communications-based prohibition in that the former targets situations that involve both greater social harm and less risk of chilling desirable behavior than those most likely to generate liability under the latter. The direct approach is also less difficult to administer, contrary to conventional wisdom.

    On reflection, these conclusions are hardly unexpected. Direct approaches tend to be superior to indirect, circumscribed ones. Analysts, enforcers, and adjudicators usually do best by asking the right question—the one of direct social concern—rather than by attempting to answer a different one. Sometimes indirect tactics turn out to be superior, but this can be ascertained only after sustained analysis that articulates the competing methods and explicitly assesses their differences. It is therefore striking that many of the topics investigated here have been so neglected.

    This book proceeds in three parts. Part I offers a fresh, in-depth exploration of competition law’s horizontal agreement requirement. Many commentators and, to a degree, courts see this command as imposing a constraint on the inquiry and largely dictating the use of a communications-based prohibition rather than a direct approach to the problem of coordinated oligopolistic price elevation. This conventional view is shown to be incoherent, with the key statutory terms and underlying concepts actually being more in accord with a direct approach. Furthermore, much doctrine as well as practice, both in court and outside, is more consistent with a broader view of the law’s prohibition. Finally, it is explained that the narrower interpretation of the agreement requirement has no analogue in modern oligopoly theory, so any attempt to maintain such a legal rule really has to be highly formalistic, divorced from economic precepts.

    With much underbrush having been removed, part II analyzes the problem of coordinated oligopolistic price elevation, starting from first principles. The initial step is to assess—more explicitly, carefully, and completely than is usually done—the nature of the social problem, including the possible costs of regulation in terms of chilling desirable behavior through the risk of false positives. The second step is detection, which, it is emphasized, can be done in a number of ways that vary across contexts in their availability and accuracy. Third, one must apply sanctions, another topic that has suffered from too little attention. Contrary to much existing commentary, emphasis here is placed on the deterrent role of remedies, rather than on their ex post ability to restore competition, because a well-functioning system will discourage most violations and prospective compliance is best achieved through the threat of sanctions, not legal injunctions that are more akin to command-and-control regulation.

    Part III explicitly compares a direct approach to the orthodox one, a communications-based prohibition. There is an important sense in which this part is not logically necessary, for part II undertakes a ground-up analysis of the problem and a communications-based prohibition is not what emerges. However, given the nearly exclusive focus on this method by commentators as well as the belief that it reflects existing law, a systematic, side-by-side comparison seems valuable and proves instructive. Setting aside cases with sharp, conclusive evidence—in which the two approaches would both assign liability—the communications-based prohibition is seen to be defective in ways that are an immediate consequence of its design: aiming at a subset of symptoms rather than at the problem itself. Specifically, this indirect method requires addressing the same detection question as under the direct approach—identifying whether oligopolistic coordination has taken place—as well as tackling the further question of whether such was accomplished by particular means, prohibited communications. This explains why decision-making is rendered more rather than less complicated. Worse, if one accepts conventional views about aspects of this analysis (which views will be questioned), the consequence is to focus liability on situations involving less social danger and a greater risk of chilling costs.

    Because the exposition of all three parts is extensive, it is helpful at the outset to provide a more detailed overview of the analysis, beginning with part I, on the law of horizontal agreements. To set the stage, suppose that firms in a concentrated industry are able to charge the monopoly price and maintain it at this level because those that contemplate cheating (cutting price to enhance market share) fear sufficiently swift and substantial retaliation to render deviation unprofitable. The firms’ actions and inactions are interdependent in that each firm’s strategic assessment is notably influenced by how it expects the other firms to react.

    A central question for competition law is whether such oligopolistic interdependence that produces supracompetitive prices should in itself be deemed a violation or whether something additional—perhaps secret negotiations producing a signed cartel agreement, perhaps less formal arrangements—should be a prerequisite to liability. Most contemporary writers believe that the law does and should require more than interdependence. It is obscure, however, just what supplement is necessary. Moreover, as many appreciate, this bounded view of the law is in tension with a rejection of formalism and an embrace of economically based competition regulation because coordinated price elevation leads to essentially the same economic consequences regardless of the particular manner of interactions that generates this outcome.

    Chapter 2 begins the investigation of the horizontal agreement question by presenting scenarios that illustrate the difficulty of defining agreement in a coherent fashion that successfully distinguishes pure interdependence (firms refrain from price cutting because of an expectation of retaliation derived from a shared appreciation of their circumstances)—deemed to be insufficient for liability—from classic cartels (firms meet secretly in hotel rooms to discuss prices and the consequences of cheating)—widely accepted to be more than sufficient. Of course, most legal categories give rise to line-drawing problems; it is notoriously difficult to distinguish similar shades of gray. The examples presented, however, are more corrosive because they demonstrate how hard it is to distinguish what many regard to be polar-opposite cases, analogous to black and white.

    This chapter also scrutinizes the concepts used in discussing horizontal agreements. Initial examination suggests that the standard meaning of terms like agreement, concerted practice, and conspiracy—each of which contemplates a mutual understanding or meeting of the minds—readily encompasses interdependence, although under some alternative definitions this is not the case. There is widespread use of a number of terms having potentially different meanings, which generates substantial confusion. Even more dysfunctional, certain words associated with one category of behavior are sometimes used to denote the opposite category. Interpreting both court opinions and commentary can be almost impossible, and there is room for interpreters to depict key passages, including important canonical statements of the doctrine, as having whatever meaning is desired, especially when these pronouncements are taken out of context. More broadly, intelligent dialogue about the agreement requirement is undermined, perhaps without the participants recognizing the extent of misunderstanding that their statements may cause or their readings may involve. To some degree, this state of affairs reflects inattention. But it also is symptomatic of underlying substantive challenges; after all, it never is easy to state with precision ideas that themselves are foggy, inconsistent, or incoherent.

    Chapter 3 examines interfirm communications that many, sometimes implicitly, take to be central in defining the law’s concept of agreement. The core problem with making the existence of communications determinative is that communication is ubiquitous, among other reasons because most actions, certainly including the sale of a good at a price, themselves communicate pertinent information. If the use of communications constitutes agreement, then pure interdependence (indeed, less) would trigger liability. Therefore, if agreement is to depend on communications and yet be more restrictive, it is necessary to specify some subcategory of communications, perhaps based on the mode of communication or its content, the use of which is necessary and sufficient to constitute agreement. It is explained that this approach is tantamount to declaring the result of price fixing to be per se legal while designating as illegal only the use of certain means—and, moreover, suspending the agreement requirement with respect to the decision to use such means, despite the fact that the same agreement requirement is what exonerates price coordination when such means are not employed. Furthermore, if regulation is to be restricted to a particular subcategory of communications, it is necessary to decide whether firms’ use of functional equivalents also gives rise to liability. If it does not, circumvention is invited. But if it does—which one might expect under a modern, nonformalistic view of the law—one returns to a prohibition on all successful interdependent coordination, for the function that is meant to be served by the communications in question is to succeed at coordination.

    The discussion of communications also considers a range of theories and bodies of evidence about language that seem pertinent but have not previously been applied to the present context. Human language is extremely flexible and adaptable, resisting efforts at regulation. It also can be difficult for outsiders to understand what is being communicated. These and other points are sharply highlighted by sign language—the very existence of which is deeply problematic for those who implicitly seek to prohibit communication that uses language and yet freely permit the use of signs (like price signaling). It is also observed that standard approaches to defining agreement, which require the presence of particular, purely symbolic communications while excluding tangible behavior that communicates, have as their underlying logic the notion that words speak louder than actions. Of course, the more familiar, opposite maxim is better rooted in common sense and, not surprisingly, in the teaching of scholars of strategy, including business strategy with regard to the interaction of firms in an oligopoly.

    Chapters 4 and 5 examine how the agreement requirement is reflected in existing doctrine. The provision of U.S. Sherman Act Section 1, which is rarely elaborated directly, does suggest some guidance, particularly through its use of the word conspiracy. This term had and continues to have an established legal meaning that is rather expansive. In fact, some of the earlier Supreme Court cases that provide seminal interpretations of Section 1 are also regarded as leading pronouncements on the more general law of conspiracy, and precisely for some of its broader features. More recent Supreme Court opinions contain more restrictive interpretations, although the agreement question was not formally before the Court in these cases and the statements themselves are difficult to give meaning. Practice in the lower courts is quite mixed. In spite of some direct pronouncements that are ambiguous or to the contrary, actual practice is often as if the law regarded successful interdependence to be illegal. Notable in this regard are the plus factors deemed sufficient to establish agreement, jury instructions on what must be found to establish an agreement, and damages rules that necessarily reflect a standard of liability due to the requisite causal nexus between liability and compensable injury. Interpretation of EU Article 101 (formerly 81) is also briefly considered. Although the details differ, it is not surprising that similar difficulties arise because the underlying economic problem is identical and the structure of the legal prohibition is almost the same.

    Chapter 6 explores what is referred to here as the paradox of proof, a phenomenon that some have previously noted but none have analyzed in depth. This paradox grows out of the interplay of two starting points: (1) deeming agreement to require more than demonstration of successful interdependence—such as by also using certain sorts of communications—and (2) needing to infer the existence of agreement from circumstantial evidence, out of a recognition that parties hide their actions from legal scrutiny. Think about the demand that these factors jointly impose. It is assumed that, in adjudication, it frequently will be impossible to observe the communications that the defendant firms employed. Nevertheless, the factfinder must infer whether or not certain means of communication were used, based on what can be observed about market conditions, notably, how conducive they are to successful oligopolistic coordination and whether such successful coordination appears to have occurred. Because the outcome, interdependent oligopoly pricing, might have come about in any number of ways, the process of making inferences about whether the unobserved communications employed by the defendants were of one type rather than another is challenging, to say the least.

    There is also a particular feature of the inference process that seems paradoxical: Evidence indicating that the conditions are more conducive to successful coordination—which makes successful price elevation more likely—may reduce the likelihood of the existence of an agreement, defined for present purposes as the use of specified means of communication rather than others. Conventional wisdom suggests that, beyond some point, the greater the danger of coordinated oligopoly pricing, the stronger will be defendants’ claim that they were able to accomplish it without using any prohibited means. Chapter 6—with later elaboration in chapter 17—explores this logic and a number of important variations in detail. The conclusion is that the information, about both oligopoly behavior in general and the particular nature of the industry and its firms, that is necessary to assess the likelihood of the use of prohibited communications is highly complex and subtle, posing a serious obstacle to factfinding. Moreover, the implications for parties’ litigation strategies are jarring. It will be highly case-dependent which party should be on which side of many factual disputes, and whichever side does make sense for each party could readily flip midstream, such as if some witness proves to be more or less powerful than the parties had anticipated. In all, careful analysis of the paradox of proof has a whimsical feel, seemingly far removed from what appears to be the standard practices of firms, their lawyers, and adjudicators. It is thus difficult to reconcile, on one hand, the reasoned implications of what many claim that the law on agreement is and should be with, on the other hand, what the law in action is in fact or with what one might ever imagine it could be.

    Chapter 7 closes part I by assessing the relationship between modern oligopoly theory and the meaning of the agreement requirement. Because competition law seeks to regulate oligopoly behavior and, moreover, to ground such regulation in modern economic understandings, it would seem to follow that, if the law’s notion of agreement reflects economic substance, the agreement requirement would correspond to a core distinction drawn in oligopoly theory. As it turns out, that theory, which is an application of game theory (particularly, that of repeated games), does have an explicit notion of agreement. But this notion refers to binding agreements and thus is irrelevant for present purposes because competition law renders horizontal price-fixing agreements void ab initio. When agreements are not taken to be automatically enforced by an outside authority, another branch of game theory is applicable. But the pertinent theory, models, and analysis are applicable equally to successful oligopolistic coordination accomplished through pure interdependence and to that effectuated in the form of a classic cartel. That is, the distinction that many would have the law make central is, as a first approximation, nonexistent in the relevant economic theory.

    Modern oligopoly theory does, however, have a central concept—whether parties’ strategies constitute an equilibrium—that may be applicable in a somewhat different manner. The concept of equilibrium is closely related to the idea of a meeting of the minds that both is at the very essence of interdependent oligopolistic coordination and constitutes a standard definition of agreement and related terms. Equating the concept of equilibrium with agreement is not without its problems, but it really is the only concept in the relevant theory that relates in a significant way to the notion of an agreement. This chapter also considers the roles of communications and of promises in oligopoly theory, finding each of potential relevance but neither hinging critically on a notion of agreement.

    It is hoped that the first part of the book advances thought on the best way to regulate coordinated oligopoly behavior through competition law. Because the near consensus of present opinion centers on a criterion—or, more likely, numerous differing criteria—of uncertain meaning and fails to appreciate many implications of the dominant view, it is important to clarify terminology, eliminate much underbrush, and begin the task of using modern oligopoly theory to analyze the problem directly. It is difficult to compare, say, liability based on interdependence with a rule requiring more if we do not know what that more is, how to identify its existence, or how it relates to the justification for limiting oligopolistic interaction. And even simple points about terminology are critical, for it is hard to assess competing arguments when they are couched in language susceptible to multiple, even opposite, interpretations. In addition, a partial but possibly substantial explanation for the almost complete avoidance of direct policy analysis in this realm seems to be the belief that existing law in most jurisdictions dictates a particular, immutable solution. Accordingly, showing that such is not the case in a number of important respects should free analysts and policy-makers to consider the problem anew.

    It is tempting to go further and conclude from the analysis in part I that a different, concrete normative conclusion is established: that the horizontal agreement requirement is best interpreted as applicable to all interdependent behavior that is successful in producing elevated prices. After all, from each of the angles considered, virtually every difficulty derives from attempting to define agreement as requiring something more, whatever that may be. But such a conclusion would be premature. Competition policy is not best advanced by relying on a formal, interpretive enterprise, even when that undertaking seems to yield an outcome that is in accord with modern economic teachings. Instead, the thesis advanced here is that competition policy should be grounded directly in economic analysis of the pertinent issues, which the remaining two parts of this book undertake.

    Part II comprises a three-step inquiry, focusing on articulation of the social problem, detection of its presence, and the application of sanctions. The first step begins in chapter 8 by examining the social welfare consequences of coordinated oligopolistic price elevation. From the outset, it is notable that none of the pertinent theory directly distinguishes between successful coordination due merely to recognized interdependence and that resulting from classic cartel behavior, or various cases in between. The harm from price coordination in terms of allocative inefficiency or loss in consumer welfare depends most directly on the extent and duration of supracompetitive pricing, not on the means of reaching or maintaining an understanding to charge the heightened price.

    From a dynamic perspective, price elevation may also cause production inefficiency on account of excessive entry. There are some settings in which additional entry could be efficient due to insufficient product variety or other difficulties in recovering fixed costs. Such benefits might sometimes justify some price elevation, but—crucially for present purposes—do not directly distinguish the means by which it is accomplished. The expectation of above-marginal-cost prices also induces a number of other kinds of investments, many (but not all) of which are efficient. Such investment tends to be encouraged by the prospect of unilateral exercises of the market power created by such activity rather than by collective price elevation that is independent of it; indeed, incentives for efficient investment may be dampened by the presence of coordinated price elevation. This distinction provides the core rationale for prohibiting price fixing while ordinarily permitting unilateral price elevation by individual firms.

    Chapter 9 presents a framework for assessing competition rules. An economic approach to limiting coordinated oligopolistic price elevation seeks to determine liability and apply sanctions based primarily on the deterrence benefits that result as well as any chilling of desirable behavior that may ensue, while also considering the expense of operating the regime. In assessing the cost of false positives, attention focuses on incidental negative behavioral effects, not on mistakes that are defined by reference to proxy legal standards and then given arbitrary weight. An example that will prove important involves imposing sanctions on firms that actually charged elevated oligopoly prices, the prospect of which deters such behavior. This outcome is favorable in terms of social welfare but under some legal standards would be deemed to be an undesirable error in cases in which the firms did not employ forbidden modes of communication. It will also be seen that examining the rate of false positives (properly conceived) provides a highly incomplete and potentially misleading (even backward) indication of how well a system is functioning, particularly with regard to achieving deterrence. In addition, the optimal legal policy depends heavily on empirical matters, such as the extent of coordinated price elevation in the economy and the potential success of various means of detecting it; some evidence is reviewed, but important gaps in knowledge remain.

    Chapters 10 and 11 explore the problem of detection, the greatest challenge in the control of interdependent oligopoly pricing. Firms naturally seek to hide illegal aspects of their behavior, and reliable indicators are not always readily obtainable by enforcers. One approach is to employ market-based evidence to identify successful oligopolistic coordination. Price elevation may be inferred from pricing changes over time, such as the observation of significant industry price increases not accompanied by corresponding changes in cost or of sharp price drops associated with price wars. Alternatively, markups might be determined from measures of price and marginal cost or inferred from the elasticity of firms’ demand curves. Note that, as with most of the analysis throughout, these inquiries do not depend on whether detected price elevation originated through classic cartel behavior.

    Also relevant to detection is the degree to which conditions are conducive to coordinated oligopoly pricing. Highly conducive conditions make inferences of successful interdependent pricing more credible whereas unconducive conditions cast doubt on its plausibility. However, due to the noisy empirical relationship between industry structure and performance as well as the possibility that conditions are highly conducive yet oligopolistic pricing is effectively deterred, conducive conditions do not in themselves strongly indicate coordinated price elevation—whereas highly unconducive conditions do significantly negate the inference. Conducive conditions also favor liability because false positives and concomitant chilling effects are less likely; unconducive conditions are more often associated with fairly competitive behavior and thus situations in which chilling effects are a greater concern. To preview chapter 17, this feature of sound detection strategy differs importantly from the results of focusing on the existence of particular interfirm communications because, under certain assumptions, more conducive conditions reduce the likelihood that such communications occurred even though they increase the magnitude of the net expected social harm from a failure to apply sanctions.

    Another route to detection looks for internal evidence of whether coordinated oligopolistic price elevation took place. In addition to attempts to observe behavior directly or to infer it from market activity, one can examine firms’ internal understandings as reflected in their agents’ thinking and actions. Yet another, more familiar form of evidence, often deriving from similar sources, concerns interfirm communications, the existence of which may likewise indicate what firms actually did. When such evidence is clear and powerful, it will generally be sufficient to establish liability, just as under a narrower communications-based prohibition. (The approaches to liability differ when such evidence is unavailable.)

    Chapter 12 emphasizes that these internal sources of information are complementary to each other and to market-based techniques. In deciding whether to assign liability in a particular case, all such evidence on detection should be considered in light of the decision-theoretic approach articulated previously. Some forms of proof are more reliable than others and give rise to different risks of particular types of errors. For example, some market-based techniques that attempt to determine firms’ marginal costs could result in adverse incentive effects in the case of underestimation, making it optimal to find liability only if the measured price elevation is substantial or other confirming evidence is present. The chapter also considers two additional matters: liability for attempts and the problem of determining which firms should be held liable.

    The analysis of sanctions in chapter 13 concentrates primarily on deterrence. In many instances, reflecting current practice, the most important instruments are fines levied by government enforcers and, where permitted, damages collected by injured parties. If the probability of sanctions and their magnitude are sufficient, most coordinated price elevation will be deterred. A major challenge in setting monetary sanctions is determining the extent of price elevation, although this magnitude will often be indicated by much of the evidence on detection considered in chapters 10 and 11. The measurement problem is conceptually the same whether price elevation was accomplished through secret meetings, mere recognition of interdependence, or in any other manner. The threat of imprisonment as well as fines assessed against individual actors can be a useful supplement, particularly in light of agency problems within firms. Injunctions are also considered. Although much academic commentary fixates on injunctive relief, it is not evident that it is important in controlling coordinated oligopoly pricing.

    Chapter 14 examines unilateral market power, a possibility set to the side in the rest of the book and ignored in most prior work on the subject. The exercise of such power sometimes constitutes a competing explanation for price elevation in oligopolistic industries. This possibility raises three questions: whether exercising unilateral market power is also usually socially undesirable and thus should be prohibited by competition law; if it is not, how one can distinguish it from coordinated price elevation; and how one should err in cases of uncertainty. Analysis focuses both on industries with homogeneous goods and on those with differentiated products, the former of which are more relevant for present purposes because coordinated pricing is generally thought to be difficult when differentiation is substantial.

    Chapter 15 addresses two additional subjects. Institutional issues, which influence the cost and accuracy of investigation and adjudication, are important in fashioning competition rules. Second, coordinated behavior may involve not only price—the focus of this book—but also nonprice terms, such as product characteristics, territories, and other dimensions of competitive strategy. The logical structure of the analysis presented throughout is largely relevant to nonprice coordination, although, as will be discussed, the relative importance of different considerations, particularly concerning detection, can differ significantly depending on the nature of the coordination involved.

    As suggested at the outset of this introduction, part II would seem to offer a complete analysis of the regulation of price fixing by considering the nature of the problem, how to detect its presence, and what remedies to apply. In the course of this investigation, the commonly advocated approach of attacking only express and perhaps also tacit agreements, variously defined, barely surfaces. That is, it does not emerge from a systematic consideration of how best to address coordinated oligopolistic price elevation. Nevertheless, it is useful to compare these methods more explicitly, which is done in part III.

    Chapter 16 begins by defining the conventional prohibition in an operational fashion. As we know from part I, this is a daunting task. Most views can be captured by supposing that the price-fixing prohibition is limited to certain sorts of interfirm communication, whether designated by mode, content, or otherwise. This formulation on its face seems problematic because it focuses not on whether the means employed in fact caused harm in a given case but rather on whether one versus another means was employed. Preliminary consideration of social welfare consequences suggests a negative assessment, for the distinction drawn has little relationship to welfare.

    Moreover, making this type of distinction central to the prohibition suggests that detection will often prove difficult, which chapter 17 indicates is indeed the case. The essential contrast with the direct approach outlined in part II is that the communications-based prohibition uses a large portion of the most relevant evidence indicative of undesirable behavior in an indirect way and also counts evidence concerning conduciveness of conditions backward, generating what chapter 6 already expounds, the paradox of proof. Specifically, under certain assumptions that many endorse, evidence of a high danger of successful coordinated oligopoly pricing exonerates firms instead of raising the likelihood that they will be subject to sanctions. It is explained in chapter 17 that, if one calibrates the burden of proof under the direct approach to find liability in the same number of situations as under the communications-based prohibition, then the direct approach dominates. The cases it targets involve both greater social danger and less risk of chilling desirable behavior than those most likely to generate liability under commentators’ favored rule.

    This comparison can be further illuminated from another perspective. If the major concern with too aggressive an approach toward coordinated oligopolistic price elevation is the risk of chilling desirable activity as a consequence of the anticipation of false positives, then the best response would naturally be to raise the burden of proof under a direct approach. The communications-based prohibition does not take this route. Instead, it requires demonstration of particular behavior that not only is hard to identify but also is not well correlated with high deterrence benefits and low chilling costs—indeed, in certain ranges, it may be negatively correlated with both. If one attempts to optimize the proof burdens (adjust the liability/no liability boundaries) under this circumscribed prohibition, one is led to reshape it into the direct approach.

    In addition, the communications-based prohibition raises the cost and complexity of investigation and adjudication. The rule requires that one not only determine the presence of interdependent oligopoly pricing—the focus of the direct approach elaborated in part II—but also identify the means by which it was accomplished. The latter compels additional effort. Also, because the difference between permitted and prohibited means is formally rather than functionally determined, there is little empirical evidence that can guide the necessary inference process, so substantial conjecture is required. As a consequence, the conventional approach—in addition to producing inferior substantive outcomes—is significantly more challenging to apply, which is ironic in light of its widely being favored on administrability grounds.

    Chapter 18 considers a number of additional subjects: the determination of sanctions under a communications-based prohibition; an alternative rule under which liability cannot be based on circumstantial evidence, contrary to the long-standing norm in competition law; implications of the contrasting approaches for other areas of competition law, such as the stringency of limits on horizontal mergers and the regulation of practices that might facilitate oligopolistic coordination; and the manner in which rapid evolution in communications technology might influence the analysis, particularly concerning detection.

    Finally, the leading three arguments offered in favor of the traditional view—although responded to in substance at various points earlier in the book—are related explicitly to the foregoing analysis. One argument asserts a difficulty in attacking purely interdependent behavior because such would involve commanding firms to behave irrationally. This criticism is mistaken because it omits consideration of deterrence: applying heavy sanctions to certain choices will change what firms find it rational to do. Another objection is that making price elevation by oligopolists illegal is inconsistent with the legality of price elevation by monopolists. This point ignores the aforementioned purpose of separate, more stringent prohibitions on group behavior and, moreover, the notion implies that classic cartels should be legal. Third, it is argued that remedies, particularly injunctive relief, directed at price elevation are problematic because they amount to price regulation. This claim is misconceived because, as mentioned, effective control is best accomplished through penalties that achieve deterrence rather than by relying on directive legal commands. However, the argument is suggestive of an important concern with competition policy regarding price fixing that is underdeveloped in the existing literature, namely, that the detection of violations can be quite difficult, raising the problem of false positives, the prospect of which chills desirable behavior. As emphasized throughout part II, this concern should indeed be central in shaping the optimal legal regime, but the analysis shows that it does not imply the desirability of the conventional approach over a direct method that takes explicit account of possible chilling costs.

    Parts II and III of this book, which contain the policy analysis, are qualitatively different from most prior work on what rule should govern coordinated oligopolistic price elevation. Indeed, as noted earlier, there is little overlap even in the topics that are addressed. The central reason for this divergence is that the focus here is not on the question that has preoccupied much previous discussion: How should we define the term ‘agreement’? Instead, this book concentrates on the question: What approach toward coordinated oligopoly pricing best promotes social welfare? In answering the latter, it is natural to proceed by examining the nature of the problem and then determining how to identify its presence and to remedy it.

    Modern competition law emphasizes real economic effects over legalistic formalities, has an open-ended, flexible expression, and could be amended. Also, as part I argues at length, a more substantive approach conforms better to the statutory language, much of the relevant precedent, and aspects of existing practice than does the more formalistic method that is widely endorsed. Even if prevailing doctrine does impose significant constraints, it is best to start by trying to determine what in principle is the most sensible way to address coordinated price elevation.

    Coming to a firm conclusion on the best competition policy toward price fixing remains quite difficult even when the problem is properly formulated and analyzed. The optimal rule depends greatly on empirical evidence in realms where existing understanding is incomplete. One set of issues concerns the extent of coordinated oligopolistic price elevation that would prevail under various regimes. Another involves the manner in which such coordinated pricing is achieved—for example, with resort to what sorts of communication—and, more broadly, how much of it can be detected, by which methods, and at what error cost. Without further knowledge, it is difficult to identify the best rule with any confidence. However, the proffered framework not only guides that decision in the interim but also sharpens the research agenda so that better strategies might be devised in the future.

    PART I

    HORIZONTAL AGREEMENTS

    2

    Defining the Problem

    To understand the meaning of horizontal agreement, it is necessary to juxtapose abstract categories and concrete situations. Accordingly, this chapter begins by offering two examples that illustrate how difficult it is to define the notion of agreement as it is conventionally understood in the competition policy literature.¹ Next, frequently used terms are defined, which is necessary given the unusually wide variance in usage, including the extreme of employing a single key term to denote opposite conceptions. Once terminology is clarified, it is possible to describe commentators’ views and thereby articulate the core questions that occupy the analysis in the remainder of the book.

    A. Illustrations

    In some instances, it is straightforward to determine the existence of an agreement, however that notion might be defined within a fairly broad range. When two parties sign a formal, legally binding contract for the sale of an object, there is undoubtedly an agreement. When two individuals, unconnected in any way, each choose which glove to put on first, there is no agreement, even if they both start with the same hand.

    Regarding horizontal agreements in competition law, the challenge is not merely that there is a line-drawing problem as with any categorical distinction. Rather, fairly common interactions raise difficult questions. Firms in an oligopolistic industry would like to raise prices above the competitive level,² ideally to a mutually optimal monopoly-like price, and to keep the price elevated—avoiding the problem of cheating to the extent possible and quickly identifying and punishing any defections that occur (the prospect of which, the firms hope, will deter cheating in the first place).³ Such firms may reap great profits if they are on the legal side of the line (even if just barely) but suffer stiff penalties if they are on the other side (even slightly). As a consequence, their strategic anticipatory behavior places great pressure on the boundary, wherever it is drawn. This section presents two sets of related scenarios in order to illustrate the tensions that arise.

    EXAMPLE 1

    As the curtain opens, our two competitors are staring intently at each other. Each sees the other’s gaze. Each is thinking (and is pretty darn sure that the other is thinking): This is ridiculous. We’ve each been charging the competitive price of $3.00 for months. We’d both make a ton more money if we were charging something higher.

    And each thinks: "Should I break the staring contest and just shout out to my competitor that this is so? Nah, why bother? It’s so obvious as to be pathetic, embarrassing. A good primal scream might get it off my chest, but the name of the game is communication and reaching an agreement to move forward, not a therapy session."

    One of the two, who will be called the Initiator, decides that it’s time to act. Initiator thinks that a good price would be $3.40 but doesn’t want to be too aggressive. So Initiator decides to go with $3.25 as an opening suggestion. Initiator proclaims, As of this very instant, until further notice, I’m going to charge all of my customers $3.25. By the way, if I change my mind, I can assure you that you will be among the first to know. There will be no secret price cuts. Never.

    The other, who will be called the Responder, is delighted. Responder thinks: Should I just go right along, accepting this invitation? Or, since I think that the ideal price is higher, should I raise the offer? Hey, why not go for it while the going’s good. Responder answers: As of this moment, until further notice, I’m going to charge all of my customers $3.35. And, if I change my mind, you will certainly be among the first to know. I will never secretly cut my price.

    Initiator is ecstatic. Initiator had hoped and suspected that Responder would answer positively. But one never knows for sure. And Responder has done one better by going up to $3.35. So, Initiator wonders: Do I respond quickly and match the offer, closing the deal, or should I go for it and press for $3.40, my view of the ideal price? What the heck, today is a good day and Responder is obviously in the spirit of cooperation. And $3.40 is hardly an in your face rejection! Initiator then declares: As of now, until further notice, I’m going to charge all of my customers $3.40. And….

    Responder answers quickly this time. Responder wasn’t sure if the right price was $3.35, $3.40, or perhaps $3.45. But hey, Initiator must think it’s $3.40, and we’re nearly symmetrically situated, so why not close the deal? Responder announces: As of now, until further notice, I’m going to charge all of my customers $3.40….

    And there our story ends. Initiator and Responder live happily, and profitably, ever after. Of course, their customers do not.

    At this point, one should ask whether the foregoing depicts an agreement. (Also consider variants, such as an express agreement.) Most, I suspect, will have little reluctance answering in the affirmative.

    But what of the fact that there is no binding contract? No signed document? No language of offer and acceptance, of agreement, of promises, and so forth? These questions do not create serious reservations. Agreements subject to competition law’s prohibition need not be binding contracts; indeed, this is an impossibility because, for agreements that involve forbidden behavior like pure price fixing, they as a consequence cannot be legally binding. Nor is writing required. Nor the use of magic words. Stating There will be no secret price cuts rather than I promise that there will be no secret price cuts is not taken to be an important distinction, and it may be viewed as meaningless in this context because, as just noted, no promise is binding in any event. Furthermore, as a practical matter, if a finding of agreement could be avoided merely by phrasing communications in the language of declarations of unilateral intent—perhaps adding for good measure formal disclaimers of any agreement—then parties, coached by lawyers as necessary, would be free to fix prices with impunity. Accordingly, our story of the two competitors would generally be regarded to involve an undoubted agreement.

    Suppose now that we change the story. Instead of a secret meeting of the principals of (the only) two competitors in a market, consider the interaction of two gas station owners located on adjacent corners in an otherwise isolated area.⁵ No words are spoken. We begin with each selling at $3.00 per gallon. Then, one morning, the owner playing the role of initiator changes the numbers displayed on the station’s large sign—visible from a block away and thus impossible to miss for the competing station owner across the street—to show a new price of $3.25. Shortly thereafter, the owner of the competing station posts $3.35 on its large sign. And so forth, until the price that each charges settles at $3.40 and remains there indefinitely. Suppose further that each entertains precisely the same thoughts as in our original story—that is, they both think it ridiculous to be selling at the competitive price, the initiator initially thought that $3.40 would be a good price but out of caution began by posting $3.25, and so on.

    Does this new scenario depict an agreement? It is almost universally accepted that it does not. Even though the consequence in terms of supracompetitive pricing is the same as in our original setting, this unfortunate result is attributed to the structural character of the market in question, not to an agreement. After all, because no agreement exists, how could it be otherwise?

    Although there is near consensus on the outcomes, this harmony does not extend to the articulation of which distinctions between the two scenarios are responsible for the demarcation: an undoubted agreement in the first and none in the second. Some would emphasize the inevitability of an oligopoly outcome in the second case, making an agreement unnecessary. Some might note the lack of any exchange of words or other forms of explicit communication in the latter setting. But, regardless of which factors are mentioned, it obviously is necessary to be able to identify one or more differences that explain why there is an agreement in one case but not in the other. Furthermore, because neither case is generally regarded to be a close call, the distinguishing features should be fairly sharp.

    Upon reflection, however, any proposed answer must be deficient. One way to see this point is to entertain the suggestion that the exposition of the second case involved a sleight of hand: specifically, the introductory sentence was inaccurate. Suppose that the two gas station owners are not players in a changed, second story. Instead, imagine that they were the principals in the original version; that is, the second story can be interpreted as just a retelling of the first, which can be seen by reviewing that play closely: At the outset, the two competitors were staring intently at each other—from across the street. Each thought the situation of two gas stations in a remote area charging the competitive price was foolish. Each would have had to shout out to the other because they were across the street, not in a hotel room. The Initiator proclaims (that is, declares publicly, gives an outward indication, to mention some standard definitions of the term)⁶ a new price of $3.25 in the clearest and most convincing manner possible, by posting that price on the station’s price sign. Obviously, any subsequent change in this price would result in the competing owner being among the first to know, and there cannot be a secret price cut in this setting. The Responder answers (acts in response to an action performed by another) and later announces (makes known publicly) its own prices, using its own price signs.

    One could augment the story and suppose that the price signs, in addition to displaying the price in large numerals, also contain, in standard-form smaller print, the words: The above price is this gas station’s price from this very instant and will continue in force until further notice. And if the owner of this station should ever wish to change the price, this can be done only by replacing this price sign with a sign showing such different price. In addition, the owner is bound to charge the price posted on this sign and no other price, that is, unless and until this sign is changed. In such a fashion, each word in the original scenario could be included. Of course, because this is the plain, unambiguous meaning of the simple sign that contains merely the price, no meaningful difference is entailed.

    This example therefore poses a sharp challenge. The simple, straightforward scenario is properly characterized in two ways: a classic, undoubted agreement, and a clear case of no agreement. Whatever distinctions one might have hypothesized to be sufficient to rationalize this difference in legal characterization must be mistaken because there is only one situation after all. Therefore, even before examining particular definitions of and variations on agreement and related terms in section B, it is apparent that the categorization problem, as conventionally understood, is quite difficult to solve, if indeed any solution is possible.

    EXAMPLE 2

    Version A. Individuals with price-setting authority at each of the firms in a fairly concentrated industry meet in a hotel room and hash out an explicit agreement on pricing: future prices, penalties for deviation, and so forth. They all speak directly, and all concur on the final outcome, which includes increasing each firm’s price from the current, competitive level to a monopoly level in one month, and this result occurs on schedule.

    Version B. This variant is the same as version A except that the language is lawyered, which is to say that there is no use of magic words like agreement or promise; instead, all statements are carefully phrased as expressions of thoughts, wishes, or unilateral intentions. No one’s understanding, however, is influenced

    Enjoying the preview?
    Page 1 of 1